Deschooling Society

IVAN ILLICH

Contents

Introduction

1 Why We Must Disestablish School

2 Phenomenology of School

3 Ritualization of Progress

4 Institutional Spectrum

5 Irrational Consistencies

6 Learning Webs

7 Rebirth of Epimethean Man

Downloaded from http://philosophy.la.psu.edu/illich/deschool/

Deschooling Society

Page # 1

Introduction

I owe my interest in public education to Everett Reimer. Until we first met in Puerto Rico
in 1958, 1 had never questioned the value of extending obligatory schooling to all people.
Together we have come to realize that for most men the right to learn is curtailed by the
obligation to attend school. The essays given at CIDOC and gathered in this book grew
out of memoranda which I submitted to him, and which we discussed during 1970, the
thirteenth year of our dialogue. The last chapter contains my afterthoughts on a
conversation with Erich Fromm on Bachofen's Mutterrecht.

Since 1967 Reimer and I have met regularly at the Center for Intercultural
Documentation (CIDOC) in Cuernavaca, Mexico. Valentine Borremans, the director of
the Center, also joined our dialogue, and constantly urged me to test our thinking against
the realities of Latin America and Africa. This book reflects her conviction that the ethos,
not just the institutions, of society ought to be "deschooled."

Universal education through schooling is not feasible. It would be no more feasible if it
were attempted by means of alternative institutions built on the style of present schools.
Neither new attitudes of teachers toward their pupils nor the proliferation of educational
hardware or software (in classroom or bedroom), nor finally the attempt to expand the
pedagogue's responsibility until it engulfs his pupils' lifetimes will deliver universal
education. The current search for new educational funnels must be reversed into the
search for their institutional inverse: educational webs which heighten the opportunity for
each one to transform each moment of his living into one of learning, sharing, and caring.
We hope to contribute concepts needed by those who conduct such counterfoil research
on education— and also to those who seek alternatives to other established service
industries.

On Wednesday mornings, during the spring and summer of 1970, 1 submitted the various
parts of this book to the participants in our CIDOC programs in Cuernavaca. Dozens of
them made suggestions or provided criticisms. Many will recognize their ideas in these
pages, especially Paulo Freire, Peter Berger, and JosZ Maria Bulnes, as well as Joseph
Fitzpatrick, John Holt, Angel Quintero, Layman Allen, Fred Goodman, Gerhard Ladner,
Didier Piveteau, Joel Spring, Augusto Salazar Bondy, and Dennis Sullivan. Among my
critics, Paul Goodman most radically obliged me to revise my thinking. Robert Silvers
provided me with brilliant editorial assistance on Chapters 1, 3, and 6, which have
appeared in The New York Review of Books.

Reimer and I have decided to publish separate views of our joint research. He is working
on a comprehensive and documented exposition, which will be subjected to several
months of further critical appraisal and be published late in 1971 by Doubleday &
Company. Dennis Sullivan, who acted as secretary at the meetings between Reimer and

Deschooling Society

Page # 2

myself, is preparing a book for publication in the spring of 1972 which will place my
argument in the context of current debate about public schooling in the United States. I
offer this volume of essays now in the hope that it will provoke additional critical
contributions to the sessions of a seminar on "Alternatives in Education" planned at
CIDOC in Cuernavaca for 1972 and 1973.

I intend to discuss some perplexing issues which are raised once we embrace the
hypothesis that society can be deschooled; to search for criteria which may help us
distinguish institutions which merit development because they support learning in a
deschooled milieu; and to clarify those personal goals which would foster the advent of
an Age of Leisure (schole) as opposed to an economy dominated by service industries.

IVAN ILLICH

CIDOC

Cuernavaca, Mexico
November, 1970

Deschooling Society

Page # 3

1

Why We Must Disestablish School

Many students, especially those who are poor, intuitively know what the schools do for
them. They school them to confuse process and substance. Once these become blurred, a
new logic is assumed: the more treatment there is, the better are the results; or, escalation
leads to success. The pupil is thereby "schooled" to confuse teaching with learning, grade
advancement with education, a diploma with competence, and fluency with the ability to
say something new. His imagination is "schooled" to accept service in place of value.
Medical treatment is mistaken for health care, social work for the improvement of
community life, police protection for safety, military poise for national security, the rat
race for productive work. Health, learning, dignity, independence, and creative endeavor
are defined as little more than the performance of the institutions which claim to serve
these ends, and their improvement is made to depend on allocating more resources to the
management of hospitals, schools, and other agencies in question.

In these essays, I will show that the institutionalization of values leads inevitably to
physical pollution, social polarization, and psychological impotence: three dimensions in
a process of global degradation and modernized misery. I will explain how this process of
degradation is accelerated when nonmaterial needs are transformed into demands for
commodities; when health, education, personal mobility, welfare, or psychological
healing are defined as the result of services or "treatments." I do this because I believe
that most of the research now going on about the future tends to advocate further
increases in the institutionalization of values and that we must define conditions which
would permit precisely the contrary to happen. We need research on the possible use of
technology to create institutions which serve personal, creative, and autonomous
interaction and the emergence of values which cannot be substantially controlled by
technocrats. We need counterfoil research to current futurology.

I want to raise the general question of the mutual definition of man's nature and the
nature of modem institutions which characterizes our world view and language. To do so,
I have chosen the school as my paradigm, and I therefore deal only indirectly with other
bureaucratic agencies of the corporate state: the consumer-family, the party, the army, the
church, the media. My analysis of the hidden curriculum of school should make it evident
that public education would profit from the deschooling of society, just as family life,
politics, security, faith, and communication would profit from an analogous process.

Deschooling Society

Page # 4

I begin my analysis, in this first essay, by trying to convey what the deschooling of a
schooled society might mean. In this context, it should be easier to understand my choice
of the five specific aspects relevant to this process with which I deal in the subsequent
chapters.

Not only education but social reality itself has become schooled. It costs roughly the
same to school both rich and poor in the same dependency. The yearly expenditure per
pupil in the slums and in the rich suburbs of any one of twenty U.S. cities lies in the same
range-and sometimes is favorable to the poor. [?* Penrose B. Jackson, Trends in
Elementary and Secondary Education Expenditures: Central City and Suburban
Comparisons 1965 to 1968, U.S. Office of Education, Office of Program and Planning
Evaluation, June 1969] Rich and poor alike depend on schools and hospitals which guide
their lives, form their world view, and define for them what is legitimate and what is not.
Both view doctoring oneself as irresponsible, learning on one's own as unreliable, and
community organization, when not paid for by those in authority, as a form of aggression
or subversion. For both groups the reliance on institutional treatment renders independent
accomplishment suspect. The progressive underdevelopment of self- and community-
reliance is even more typical in Westchester than it is in the northeast of Brazil.
Everywhere not only education but society as a whole needs "deschooling."

Welfare bureaucracies claim a professional, political, and financial monopoly over the
social imagination, setting standards of what is valuable and what is feasible. This
monopoly is at the root of the modernization of poverty. Every simple need to which an
institutional answer is found permits the invention of a new class of poor and a new
definition of poverty. Ten years ago in Mexico it was the normal thing to be bom and to
die in one's own home and to be buried by one's friends. Only the soul's needs were taken
care of by the institutional church. Now to begin and end life at home become signs
either of poverty or of special privilege. Dying and death have come under the
institutional management of doctors and undertakers.

Once basic needs have been translated by a society into demands for scientifically
produced commodities, poverty is defined by standards which the technocrats can change
at will. Poverty then refers to those who have fallen behind an advertised ideal of
consumption in some important respect. In Mexico the poor are those who lack three
years of schooling, and in New York they are those who lack twelve.

The poor have always been socially powerless. The increasing reliance on institutional
care adds a new dimension to their helplessness: psychological impotence, the inability to
fend for themselves. Peasants on the high plateau of the Andes are exploited by the
landlord and the merchant-once they settle in Lima they are, in addition, dependent on
political bosses, and disabled by their lack of schooling. Modernized poverty combines
the lack of power over circumstances with a loss of personal potency. This modernization
of poverty is a world-wide phenomenon, and lies at the root of contemporary
underdevelopment. Of course it appears under different guises in rich and in poor
countries.

Deschooling Society

Page # 5

It is probably most intensely felt in U.S. cities. Nowhere else is poverty treated at greater
cost. Nowhere else does the treatment of poverty produce so much dependence, anger,
frustration, and further demands. And nowhere else should it be so evident that poverty-
once it has become modemized-has become resistant to treatment with dollars alone and
requires an institutional revolution.

Today in the United States the black and even the migrant can aspire to a level of
professional treatment which would have been unthinkable two generations ago, and
which seems grotesque to most people in the Third World. For instance, the U.S. poor
can count on a truant officer to return their children to school until they reach seventeen,
or on a doctor to assign them to a hospital bed which costs sixty dollars per day-the
equivalent of three months' income for a majority of the people in the world. But such
care only makes them dependent on more treatment, and renders them increasingly
incapable of organizing their own lives around their own experiences and resources
within their own communities.

The poor in the United States are in a unique position to speak about the predicament
which threatens all the poor in a modernizing world. They are making the discovery that
no amount of dollars can remove the inherent destructiveness of welfare institutions, once
the professional hierarchies of these institutions have convinced society that their
ministrations are morally necessary. The poor in the U.S. inner city can demonstrate from
their own experience the fallacy on which social legislation in a "schooled" society is
built.

Supreme Court Justice William 0. Douglas observed that "the only way to establish an
institution is to finance it." The corollary is also true. Only by channeling dollars away
from the institutions which now treat health, education, and welfare can the further
impoverishment resulting from their disabling side effects be stopped.

This must be kept in mind when we evaluate federal aid pro-grams. As a case in point,
between 1965 and 1968 over three billion dollars were spent in U.S. schools to offset the
disadvantages of about six million children. The program is known as Title One. It is the
most expensive compensatory program ever attempted anywhere in education, yet no
significant improvement can be detected in the learning of these "disadvantaged"
children. Compared with their classmates from middle income homes, they have fallen
further behind. Moreover, in the course of this program, professionals discovered an
additional ten million children laboring under economic and educational handicaps. More
reasons for claiming more federal funds are now at hand.

This total failure to improve the education of the poor despite more costly treatment can
be explained in three ways:

  1. Three billion dollars are insufficient to improve the perform-ance of six
    million children by a measurable amount; or

Deschooling Society

Page # 6

  1. The money was incompetently spent: different curricula, better
    administration, further concentration of the funds on the poor child, and
    more research are needed and would do the trick; or

  2. Educational disadvantage cannot be cured by relying on education
    within the school.

The first is certainly true so long as the money has been spent through the school budget.
The money indeed went to the schools which contained most of the disadvantaged
children, but it was not spent on the poor children themselves. These children for whom
the money was intended comprised only about half of those who were attending the
schools that added the federal subsidies to their budgets. Thus the money was spent for
custodial care, indoctrination and the selection of social roles, as well as education, all of
which functions are inextricably mingled in the physical plants, curricula, teachers,
administrators, and other key components of these schools, and, therefore, in their
budgets.

The added funds enabled schools to cater disproportionately to the satisfaction of the
relatively richer children who were "disadvantaged" by having to attend school in the
company of the poor. At best a small fraction of each dollar intended to remedy a poor
child's disadvantages in learning could reach the child through the school budget.

It might be equally true that the money was incompetently spent. But even unusual
incompetence cannot beat that of the school system. Schools by their very structure resist
the concentration of privilege on those otherwise disadvantaged. Special curricula,
separate classes, or longer hours only constitute more discrimination at a higher cost.

Taxpayers are not yet accustomed to permitting three billion dollars to vanish from HEW
as if it were the Pentagon. The present Administration may believe that it can afford the
wrath of educators. Middle-class Americans have nothing to lose if the program is cut.
Poor parents think they do, but, even more, they are demanding control of the funds
meant for their children. A logical way of cutting the budget and, one hopes, of
increasing benefits is a system of tuition grants such as that proposed by Milton Friedman
and others. Funds would be channeled to the beneficiary, enabling him to buy his share of
the schooling of his choice. If such credit were limited to purchases which fit into a
school curriculum, it would tend to provide greater equality of treatment, but would not
thereby increase the equality of social claims.

It should be obvious that even with schools of equal quality a poor child can seldom catch
up with a rich one. Even if they attend equal schools and begin at the same age, poor
children lack most of the educational opportunities which are casually available to the
middle-class child. These advantages range from conversation and books in the home to
vacation travel and a different sense of oneself, and apply, for the child who enjoys them,
both in and out of school. So the poorer student will generally fall behind so long as he

Deschooling Society

Page # 7

depends on school for advancement or learning. The poor need funds to enable them to
learn, not to get certified for the treatment of their alleged disproportionate deficiencies.

All this is true in poor nations as well as in rich ones, but there it appears under a
different guise. Modernized poverty in poor nations affects more people more visibly but
also-for the moment-more superficially. Two-thirds of all children in Latin America leave
school before finishing the fifth grade, but these "desertores" are not therefore as badly
off as they would be in the United States.

Few countries today remain victims of classical poverty, which was stable and less
disabling. Most countries in Latin America have reached the "take-off" point toward
economic development and competitive consumption, and thereby toward modernized
poverty: their citizens have learned to think rich and live poor. Their laws make six to ten
years of school obligatory. Not only in Argentina but also in Mexico or Brazil the
average citizen defines an adequate education by North American standards, even though
the chance of getting such prolonged schooling is limited to a tiny minority. In these
countries the majority is already hooked on school, that is, they are schooled in a sense of
inferiority toward the better- schooled. Their fanaticism in favor of school makes it
possible to exploit them doubly: it permits increasing allocation of public funds for the
education of a few and increasing acceptance of social control by the many.

Paradoxically, the belief that universal schooling is absolutely necessary is most firmly
held in those countries where the fewest people have been-and will be-served by schools.
Yet in Latin America different paths toward education could still be taken by the majority
of parents and children. Proportionately, national savings invested in schools and teachers
might be higher than in rich countries, but these investments are totally insufficient to
serve the majority by making even four years of school attendance possible. Fidel Castro
talks as if he wanted to go in the direction of deschooling when he promises that by 1980
Cuba will be able to dissolve its university since all of life in Cuba will be an educational
experience. At the grammar-school and high-school level, however, Cuba, like all other
Latin- American countries, acts as though passage through a period defined as the "school
age" were an unquestionable goal for all, delayed merely by a temporary shortage of
resources.

The twin deceptions of increased treatment, as actually provided in the United States and
as merely promised in Latin America complement each other. The Northern poor are
being disabled by the same twelve-year treatment whose lack brands the Southern poor as
hopelessly backward. Neither in North America nor in Latin America do the poor get
equality from obligatory schools. But in both places the mere existence of school
discourages and disables the poor from taking control of their own learning. All over the
world the school has an anti-educational effect on society: school is recognized as the
institution which specializes in education. The failures of school are taken by most people
as a proof that education is a very costly, very complex, always arcane, and frequently
almost impossible task.

Deschooling Society

Page # 8

School appropriates the money, men, and good will available for education and in
addition discourages other institutions from assuming educational tasks. Work, leisure,
politics, city living, and even family life depend on schools for the habits and knowledge
they presuppose, instead of becoming themselves the means of education. Simultaneously
both schools and the other institutions which depend on them are priced out of the
market.

In the United States the per capita costs of schooling have risen almost as fast as the cost
of medical treatment. But increased treatment by both doctors and teachers has shown
steadily declining results. Medical expenses concentrated on those above forty-five have
doubled several times over a period of forty years with a resulting 3 percent increase in
life expectancy in men. The increase in educational expenditures has produced even
stranger results; otherwise President Nixon could not have been moved this spring to
promise that every child shall soon have the "Right to Read" before leaving school.

In the United States it would take eighty billion dollars per year to provide what
educators regard as equal treatment for all in grammar and high school. This is well over
twice the $36 billion now being spent. Independent cost projections prepared at HEW and
the University of Florida indicate that by 1974 the comparable figures will be $107
billion as against the $45 billion now projected, and these figures wholly omit the
enormous costs of what is called "higher education," for which demand is growing even
faster. The United States, which spent nearly eighty billion dollars in 1969 for "defense"
including its deployment in Vietnam, is obviously too poor to provide equal schooling.
The President's committee for the study of school finance should ask not how to support
or how to trim such increasing costs, but how they can be avoided.

Equal obligatory schooling must be recognized as at least economically unfeasible. In
Latin America the amount of public money spent on each graduate student is between
350 and 1,500 times the amount spent on the median citizen (that is, the citizen who
holds the middle ground between the poorest and the richest). In the United States the
discrepancy is smaller, but the discrimination is keener. The richest parents, some 10
percent, can afford private education for their children and help them to benefit from
foundation grants. But in addition they obtain ten times the per capita amount of public
funds if this is compared with the per capita expenditure made on the children of the 10
percent who are poorest. The principal reasons for this are that rich children stay longer
in school, that a year in a university is disproportionately more expensive than a year in
high school, and that most private universities depend-at least indirectly-on tax-derived
finances.

Obligatory schooling inevitably polarizes a society; it also grades the nations of the world
according to an international caste system. Countries are rated like castes whose
educational dignity is determined by the average years of schooling of its citizens, a
rating which is closely related to per capita gross national product, and much more
painful.

Deschooling Society

Page # 9

The paradox of the schools is evident: increased expenditure escalates their
destructiveness at home and abroad. This paradox must be made a public issue. It is now
generally accepted that the physical environment will soon be destroyed by biochemical
pollution unless we reverse current trends in the production of physical goods. It should
also be recognized that social and personal life is threatened equally by HEW pollution,
the inevitable by-product of obligatory and competitive consumption of welfare.

The escalation of the schools is as destructive as the escalation of weapons but less
visibly so. Everywhere in the world school costs have risen faster than enrollments and
faster than the GNP; everywhere expenditures on school fall even further behind the
expectations of parents, teachers, and pupils. Everywhere this situation discourages both
the motivation and the financing for large-scale planning for nonschooled learning. The
United States is proving to the world that no country can be rich enough to afford a
school system that meets the demands this same system creates simply by existing,
because a successful school system schools parents and pupils to the supreme value of a
larger school system, the cost of which increases disproportionately as higher grades are
in demand and become scarce.

Rather than calling equal schooling temporarily unfeasible, we must recognize that it is,
in principle, economically absurd, and that to attempt it is intellectually emasculating,
socially polarizing, and destructive of the credibility of the political system which
promotes it. The ideology of obligatory schooling admits of no logical limits. The White
House recently provided a good example. Dr. Hutschnecker, the "psychiatrist" who
treated Mr. Nixon before he was qualified as a candidate, recommended to the President
that all children between six and eight be professionally examined to ferret out those who
have destructive tendencies, and that obligatory treatment be provided for them. If
necessary, their re-education in special institutions should be required. This memorandum
from his doctor the President sent for evaluation to HEW. Indeed, preventive
concentration camps for predelinquents would be a logical improvement over the school
system.

Equal educational opportunity is, indeed, both a desirable and a feasible goal, but to
equate this with obligator;' schooling is to confuse salvation with the Church. School has
become the world religion of a modernized proletariat, and makes futile promises of
salvation to the poor of the technological age. The nation-state has adopted it, drafting all
citizens into a graded curriculum leading to sequential diplomas not unlike the initiation
rituals and hieratic promotions of former times. The modern state has assumed the duty
of enforcing the judgment of its educators through well-meant truant officers and job
requirements, much as did the Spanish kings who enforced the judgments of their
theologians through the conquistadors and the Inquisition.

Two centuries ago the United States led the world in a movement to disestablish the
monopoly of a single church. Now we need the constitutional disestablishment of the
monopoly of the school, and thereby of a system which legally combines prejudice with
discrimination. The first article of a bill of rights for a modern, humanist society would
correspond to the First Amendment to the U.S. Constitution: "The State shall make no

Deschooling Society

Page # 10

law with respect to the establishment of education." There shall be no ritual obligatory for
all.

To make this disestablishment effective, we need a law forbidding discrimination in
hiring, voting, or admission to centers of learning based on previous attendance at some
curriculum. This guarantee would not exclude performance tests of competence for a
function or role, but would remove the present absurd discrimination in favor of the
person who leams a given skill with the largest expenditure of public funds or what is
equally likely has been able to obtain a diploma which has no relation to any useful skill
or job. Only by protecting the citizen from being disqualified by anything in his career in
school can a constitutional disestablishment of school become psychologically effective.

Neither learning nor justice is promoted by schooling because educators insist on
packaging instruction with certification. Learning and the assignment of social roles are
melted into schooling. Yet to learn means to acquire a new skill or insight, while
promotion depends on an opinion which others have formed. Learning frequently is the
result of instruction, but selection for a role or category in the job market increasingly
depends on mere length of attendance.

Instruction is the choice of circumstances which facilitate learning. Roles are assigned by
setting a curriculum of conditions which the candidate must meet if he is to make the
grade. School links instruction but not learning to these roles. This is neither reasonable
nor liberating. It is not reasonable because it does not link relevant qualities or
competences to roles, but rather the process by which such qualities are supposed to be
acquired. It is not liberating or educational because school reserves instruction to those
whose every step in learning fits previously approved measures of social control.

Curriculum has always been used to assign social rank. At times it could be prenatal:
karma ascribes you to a caste and lineage to the aristocracy. Curriculum could take the
form of a ritual, of sequential sacred ordinations, or it could consist of a succession of
feats in war or hunting, or further advancement could be made to depend on a series of
previous princely favors. Universal schooling was meant to detach role assignment from
personal life history: it was meant to give everybody an equal chance to any office. Even
now many people wrongly believe that school ensures the dependence of public trust on
relevant learning achievements. However, instead of equalizing chances, the school
system has monopolized their distribution.

To detach competence from curriculum, inquiries into a man's learning history must be
made taboo, like inquiries into his political affiliation, church attendance, lineage, sex
habits, or racial background. Laws forbidding discrimination on the basis of prior
schooling must be enacted. Laws, of course, cannot stop prejudice against the
unschooled-nor are they meant to force anyone to intermarry with an autodidact but they
can discourage unjustified discrimination.

A second major illusion on which the school system rests is that most learning is the
result of teaching. Teaching, it is true, may contribute to certain kinds of learning under

Deschooling Society

Page # 11

certain circumstances. But most people acquire most of their knowledge outside school,
and in school only insofar as school, in a few rich countries, has become their place of
confinement during an increasing part of their lives.

Most learning happens casually, and even most intentional learning is not the result of
programmed instruction. Normal children learn their first language casually, although
faster if their parents pay attention to them. Most people who learn a second language
well do so as a result of odd circumstances and not of sequential teaching. They go to live
with their grandparents, they travel, or they fall in love with a foreigner. Fluency in
reading is also more often than not a result of such extracurricular activities. Most people
who read widely, and with pleasure, merely believe that they learned to do so in school;
when challenged, they easily discard this illusion.

But the fact that a great deal of learning even now seems to happen casually and as a by-
product of some other activity defined as work or leisure does not mean that planned
learning does not benefit from planned instruction and that both do not stand in need of
improvement. The strongly motivated student who is faced with the task of acquiring a
new and complex skill may benefit greatly from the discipline now associated with the
old-fashioned schoolmaster who taught reading, Hebrew, catechism, or multiplication by
rote. School has now made this kind of drill teaching rare and disreputable, yet there are
many skills which a motivated student with normal aptitude can master in a matter of a
few months if taught in this traditional way. This is as true of codes as of their
encipherment; of second and third languages as of reading and writing; and equally of
special languages such as algebra, computer programming, chemical analysis, or of
manual skills like typing, watchmaking, plumbing, wiring, TV repair; or for that matter
dancing, driving, and diving.

In certain cases acceptance into a learning program aimed at a specific skill might
presuppose competence in some other skill, but it should certainly not be made to depend
upon the process by which such prerequisite skills were acquired. TV repair presupposes
literacy and some math; diving, good swimming; and driving, very little of either.

Progress in learning skills is measurable. The optimum resources in time and materials
needed by an average motivated adult can be easily estimated. The cost of teaching a
second Western European language to a high level of fluency ranges between four and
six hundred dollars in the United States, and for an Oriental tongue the time needed for
instruction might be doubled. This would still be very little compared with the cost of
twelve years of schooling in New York City (a condition for acceptance of a worker into
the Sanitation Department) almost fifteen thousand dollars. No doubt not only the teacher
but also the printer and the pharmacist protect their trades through the public illusion that
training for them is very expensive.

At present schools pre-empt most educational funds. Drill instruction which costs less
than comparable schooling is now a privilege of those rich enough to bypass the schools,
and those whom either the army or big business sends through in-service training. In a
program of progressive deschooling of U.S. education, at first the resources available for

Deschooling Society

Page # 12

drill training would be limited. But ultimately there should be no obstacle for anyone at
any time of his life to be able to choose instruction among hundreds of definable skills at
public expense.

Right now educational credit good at any skill center could be provided in limited
amounts for people of all ages, and not just to the poor. I envisage such credit in the form
of an educational passport or an "edu-credit card" provided to each citizen at birth. In
order to favor the poor, who probably would not use their yearly grants early in life, a
provision could be made that interest accrued to later users of cumulated "entitlements."
Such credits would permit most people to acquire the skills most in demand, at their
convenience, better, faster, cheaper, and with fewer undesirable side effects than in
school.

Potential skill teachers are never scarce for long because, on the one hand, demand for a
skill grows only with its performance within a community and, on the other, a man
exercising a skill could also teach it. But, at present, those using skills which are in
demand and do require a human teacher are discouraged from sharing these skills with
others. This is done either by teachers who monopolize the licenses or by unions which
protect their trade interests. Skill centers which would be judged by customers on their
results, and not on the personnel they employ or the process they use, would open
unsuspected working opportunities, frequently even for those who are now considered
unemployable. Indeed, there is no reason why such skill centers should not be at the work
place itself, with the employer and his work force supplying instruction as well as jobs to
those who choose to use their educational credits in this way.

In 1956 there arose a need to teach Spanish quickly to several hundred teachers, social
workers, and ministers from the New York Archdiocese so that they could communicate
with Puerto Ricans. My friend Gerry Morris announced over a Spanish radio station that
he needed native speakers from Harlem. Next day some two hundred teen-agers lined up
in front of his office, and he selected four dozen of them-many of them school dropouts.
He trained them in the use of the U.S. Foreign Service Institute (FSI) Spanish manual,
designed for use by linguists with graduate training, and within a week his teachers were
on their own-each in charge of four New Yorkers who wanted to speak the language.
Within six months the mission was accomplished. Cardinal Spellman could claim that he
had 127 parishes in which at least three staff members could communicate in Spanish. No
school program could have matched these results.

Skill teachers are made scarce by the belief in the value of licenses. Certification
constitutes a form of market manipulation and is plausible only to a schooled mind. Most
teachers of arts and trades are less skillful, less inventive, and less communicative than
the best craftsmen and tradesmen. Most high-school teachers of Spanish or French do not
speak the language as correctly as their pupils might after half a year of competent drills.
Experiments conducted by Angel Quintero in Puerto Rico suggest that many young teen-
agers, if given the proper incentives, programs, and access to tools, are better than most
schoolteachers at introducing their peers to the scientific exploration of plants, stars, and
matter, and to the discovery of how and why a motor or a radio functions.

Deschooling Society

Page # 13

Opportunities for skill-learning can be vastly multiplied if we open the "market." This
depends on matching the right teacher with the right student when he is highly motivated
in an intelligent program, without the constraint of curriculum.

Free and competing drill instruction is a subversive blasphemy to the orthodox educator.

It dissociates the acquisition of skills from "humane" education, which schools package
together, and thus it promotes unlicensed learning no less than unlicensed teaching for
unpredictable purposes.

There is currently a proposal on record which seems at first to make a great deal of sense.
It has been prepared by Christopher Jencks of the Center for the Study of Public Policy
and is sponsored by the Office of Economic Opportunity. It proposes to put educational
"entitlements" or tuition grants into the hands of parents and students for expenditure in
the schools of their choice. Such individual entitlements could indeed be an important
step in the right direction. We need a guarantee of the right of each citizen to an equal
share of tax-derived educational resources, the right to verify this share, and the right to
sue for it if denied. It is one form of a guarantee against regressive taxation.

The Jencks proposal, however, begins with the ominous statement that "conservatives,
liberals, and radicals have all complained at one time or another that the American
educational system gives professional educators too little incentive to provide high
quality education to most children." The proposal condemns itself by proposing tuition
grants which would have to be spent on schooling.

This is like giving a lame man a pair of crutches and stipulating that he use them only if
the ends are tied together. As the proposal for tuition grants now stands, it plays into the
hands not only of the professional educators but of racists, promoters of religious schools,
and others whose interests are socially divisive. Above all, educational entitlements
restricted to use within schools play into the hands of all those who want to continue to
live in a society in which social advancement is tied not to proven knowledge but to the
learning pedigree by which it is supposedly acquired. This discrimination in favor of
schools which dominates Jencks's discussion on refinancing education could discredit
one of the most critically needed principles for educational reform: the return of initiative
and accountability for learning to the learner or his most immediate tutor.

The deschooling of society implies a recognition of the two-faced nature of learning. An
insistence on skill drill alone could be a disaster; equal emphasis must be placed on other
kinds of learning. But if schools are the wrong places for learning a skill, they are even
worse places for getting an education. School does both tasks badly, partly because it
does not distinguish between them. School is inefficient in skill instruction especially
because it is curricular. In most schools a program which is meant to improve one skill is
chained always to another irrelevant task. History is tied to advancement in math, and
class attendance to the right to use the playground.

Schools are even less efficient in the arrangement of the circumstances which encourage
the open-ended, exploratory use of acquired skills, for which I will reserve the term

Deschooling Society

Page # 14

"liberal education." The main reason for this is that school is obligatory and becomes
schooling for schooling's sake: an enforced stay in the company of teachers, which pays
off in the doubtful privilege of more such company. Just as skill instruction must be freed
from curricular restraints, so must liberal education be dissociated from obligatory
attendance. Both skill-learning and education for inventive and creative behavior can be
aided by institutional arrangement, but they are of a different, frequently opposed nature.

Most skills can be acquired and improved by drills, because skill implies the mastery of
definable and predictable behavior. Skill instruction can rely, therefore, on the simulation
of circumstances in which the skill will be used. Education in the exploratory and
creative use of skills, however, cannot rely on drills. Education can be the outcome of
instruction, though instruction of a kind fundamentally opposed to drill. It relies on the
relationship between partners who already have some of the keys which give access to
memories stored in and by the community. It relies on the critical intent of all those who
use memories creatively. It relies on the surprise of the unexpected question which opens
new doors for the inquirer and his partner.

The skill instructor relies on the arrangement of set circumstances which permit the
learner to develop standard responses. The educational guide or master is concerned with
helping matching partners to meet so that learning can take place. He matches individuals
starting from their own, unresolved questions. At the most he helps the pupil to formulate
his puzzlement since only a clear statement will give him the power to find his match,
moved like him, at the moment, to explore the same issue in the same context.

Matching partners for educational purposes initially seems more difficult to imagine than
finding skill instructors and partners for a game. One reason is the deep fear which school
has implanted in us, a fear which makes us censorious. The unlicensed exchange of
skills-even undesirable skills-is more predictable and therefore seems less dangerous than
the unlimited opportunity for meeting among people who share an issue which for them,
at the moment, is socially, intellectually, and emotionally important.

The Brazilian teacher Paulo Freire knows this from experience. He discovered that any
adult can begin to read in a matter of forty hours if the first words he deciphers are
charged with political meaning. Freire trains his teachers to move into a village and to
discover the words which designate current important issues, such as the access to a well
or the compound interest on the debts owed to the patron. In the evening the villagers
meet for the discussion of these key words. They begin to realize that each word stays on
the blackboard even after its sound has faded. The letters continue to unlock reality and to
make it manageable as a problem. I have frequently witnessed how discussants grow in
social awareness and how they are impelled to take political action as fast as they learn to
read. They seem to take reality into their hands as they write it down.

I remember the man who complained about the weight of pencils: they were difficult to
handle because they did not weigh as much as a shovel; and I remember another who on
his way to work stopped with his Companions and wrote the word they were discussing
with his hoe on the ground: "agua. " Since 1962 my friend Freire has moved from exile to

Deschooling Society

Page # 15

exile, mainly because he refuses to conduct his sessions around words which are
preselected by approved educators, rather than those which his discussants bring to the
class.

The educational matchmaking among people who have been successfully schooled is a
different task. Those who do not need such assistance are a minority, even among the
readers of serious journals. The majority cannot and should not be rallied for discussion
around a slogan, a word, or a picture. But the idea remains the same: they should be able
to meet around a problem chosen and defined by their own initiative. Creative,
exploratory learning requires peers currently puzzled about the same terms or problems.
Large universities make the futile attempt to match them by multiplying their courses,
and they generally fail since they are bound to curriculum, course structure, and
bureaucratic administration. In schools, including universities, most resources are spent
to purchase the time and motivation of a limited number of people to take up
predetermined problems in a ritually defined setting. The most radical alternative to
school would be a network or service which gave each man the same opportunity to share
his current concern with others motivated by the same concern.

Let me give, as an example of what I mean, a description of how an intellectual match
might work in New York City. Each man, at any given moment and at a minimum price,
could identify himself to a computer with his address and telephone number, indicating
the book, article, film, or recording on which he seeks a partner for discussion. Within
days he could receive by mail the list of others who recently had taken the same
initiative. This list would enable him by telephone to arrange for a meeting with persons
who initially would be known exclusively by the fact that they requested a dialogue about
the same subject.

Matching people according to their interest in a particular title is radically simple. It
permits identification only on the basis of a mutual desire to discuss a statement recorded
by a third person, and it leaves the initiative of arranging the meeting to the individual.
Three objections are usually raised against this skeletal purity. I take them up not only to
clarify the theory that I want to illustrate by my proposal for they highlight the deep-
seated resistance to deschooling education, to separating learning from social control but
also because they may help to suggest existing resources which are not now used for
learning purposes.

The first objection is: Why cannot self-identification be based also on an idea or an
issue? Certainly such subjective terms could also be used in a computer system. Political
parties, churches, unions, clubs, neighborhood centers, and professional societies already
organize their educational activities in this way and in effect they act as schools. They all
match people in order to explore certain "themes"; and these are dealt with in courses,
seminars, and curricula in which presumed "common interests" are prepackaged. Such
theme-matching is by definition teacher-centered: it requires an authoritarian presence to
define for the participants the starting point for their discussion.

Deschooling Society

Page # 16

By contrast, matching by the title of a book, film, etc., in its pure form leaves it to the
author to define the special language, the terms, and the framework within which a given
problem or fact is stated; and it enables those who accept this starting point to identify
themselves to one another. For instance, matching people around the idea of "cultural
revolution" usually leads either to confusion or to demagoguery. On the other hand,
matching those interested in helping each other understand a specific article by Mao,
Marcuse, Freud, or Goodman stands in the great tradition of liberal learning from Plato's
Dialogues, which are built around presumed statements by Socrates, to Aquinas's
commentaries on Peter the Lombard. The idea of matching by title is thus radically
different from the theory on which the "Great Books" clubs, for example, were built:
instead of relying on the selection by some Chicago professors, any two partners can
choose any book for further analysis.

The second objection asks: Why not let the identification of match seekers include
information on age, background, world view, competence, experience, or other defining
characteristics? Again, there is no reason why such discriminatory restrictions could not
and should not be built into some of the many universities-with or without walls-which
could use title-matching as their basic organizational device. I could conceive of a system
designed to encourage meetings of interested persons at which the author of the book
chosen would be present or represented; or a system which guaranteed the presence of a
competent adviser; or one to which only students registered in a department or school had
access; or one which permitted meetings only between people who defined their special
approach to the title under discussion. Advantages for achieving specific goals of
learning could be found for each of these restrictions. But I fear that, more often than not,
the real reason for proposing such restrictions is contempt arising from the presumption
that people are ignorant: educators want to avoid the ignorant meeting the ignorant
around a text which they may not understand and which they read only because they are
interested in it.

The third objection: Why not provide match seekers with incidental assistance that will
facilitate their meetings-with space, schedules, screening, and protection? This is now
done by schools with all the inefficiency characterizing large bureaucracies. If we left the
initiative for meetings to the match seekers themselves, organizations which nobody now
classifies as educational would probably do the job much better. I think of restaurant
owners, publishers, telephone-answering services, department store managers, and even
commuter train executives who could promote their services by rendering them attractive
for educational meetings.

At a first meeting in a coffee shop, say, the partners might establish their identities by
placing the book under discussion next to their cups. People who took the initiative to
arrange for such meetings would soon learn what items to quote to meet the people they
sought. The risk that the self-chosen discussion with one or several strangers might lead
to a loss of time, disappointment, or even unpleasantness is certainly smaller than the
same risk taken by a college applicant. A computer arranged meeting to discuss an article
in a national magazine, held in a coffee shop off Fourth Avenue, would obligate none of
the participants to stay in the company of his new acquaintances for longer than it took to

Deschooling Society

Page# 17

drink a cup of coffee, nor would he have to meet any of them ever again. The chance that
it would help to pierce the opaqueness of life in a modem city and further new friendship,
self-chosen work, and critical reading is high. (The fact that a record of personal readings
and meetings could be obtained thus by the FBI is undeniable; that this should still worry
anybody in 1970 is only amusing to a free man, who willy-nilly contributes his share in
order to drown snoopers in the irrelevancies they gather.)

Both the exchange of skills and matching of partners are based on the assumption that
education for all means education by all. Not the draft into a specialized institution but
only the mobilization of the whole population can lead to popular culture. The equal right
of each man to exercise his competence to learn and to instruct is now pre-empted by
certified teachers. The teachers' competence, in turn, is restricted to what may be done in
school. And, further, work and leisure are alienated from each other as a result: the
spectator and the worker alike are supposed to arrive at the work place all ready to fit into
a routine prepared for them. Adaptation in the form of a product's design, instruction, and
publicity shapes them for their role as much as formal education by schooling. A radical
alternative to a schooled society requires not only new formal mechanisms for the formal
acquisition of skills and their educational use. A deschooled society implies a new
approach to incidental or informal education.

Incidental education cannot any longer return to the forms which learning took in the
village or the medieval town. Traditional society was more like a set of concentric circles
of meaningful structures, while modem man must learn how to find meaning in many
structures to which he is only marginally related. In the village, language and architecture
and work and religion and family customs were consistent with one another, mutually
explanatory and reinforcing. To grow into one implied a growth into the others. Even
specialized apprenticeship was a by-product of specialized activities, such as shoemaking
or the singing of psalms. If an apprentice never became a master or a scholar, he still
contributed to making shoes or to making church services solemn. Education did not
compete for time with either work or leisure. Almost all education was complex, lifelong,
and unplanned.

Contemporary society is the result of conscious designs, and educational opportunities
must be designed into them. Our reliance on specialized, full-time instruction through
school will now decrease, and we must find more ways to learn and teach: the
educational quality of all institutions must increase again. But this is a very ambiguous
forecast. It could mean that men in the modem city will be increasingly the victims of an
effective process of total instruction and manipulation once they are deprived of even the
tenuous pretense of critical independence which liberal schools now provide for at least
some of their pupils.

It could also mean that men will shield themselves less behind certificates acquired in
school and thus gain in courage to "talk back" and thereby control and instruct the
institutions in which they participate. To ensure the latter we must learn to estimate the
social value of work and leisure by the educational give-and. take for which they offer
opportunity. Effective participation in the politics of a street, a work place, the library, a

Deschooling Society

Page# 18

news program, or a hospital is therefore the best measuring stick to evaluate their level as
educational institutions.

I recently spoke to a group of junior-high-school students in the process of organizing a
resistance movement to their obligatory draft into the next class. Their slogan was
"participation not simulation." They were disappointed that this was understood as a
demand for less rather than for more education, and reminded me of the resistance which
Karl Marx put up against a passage in the Gotha program which-one hundred years ago
wanted to outlaw child labor. He opposed the proposal in the interest of the education of
the young, which could happen only at work. If the greatest fruit of man's labor should be
the education he receives from it and the opportunity which work gives him to initiate the
education of others, then the alienation of modern society in a pedagogical sense is even
worse than its economic alienation.

The major obstacle on the way to a society that truly educates was well defined by a
black friend of mine in Chicago, who told me that our imagination was "all schooled up."
We permit the state to ascertain the universal educational deficiencies of its citizens and
establish one specialized agency to treat them. We thus share in the dyl5

Deschooling Society

Page # 19

2

Phenomenology of School

Some words become so flexible that they cease to be useful "School" and "teaching" are
such terms. Like an amoeba they fit into almost any interstice of the language. ABM will
teach the Russians, IBM will teach Negro children, and the army can become the school
of a nation.

The search for alternatives in education must therefore start with an agreement on what it
is we mean by "school." This might be done in several ways. We could begin by listing
the latent functions performed by modern school systems, such as custodial care,
selection, indoctrination, and learning. We could make a client analysis and verify which
of these latent functions render a service or a disservice to teachers, employers, children,
parents, or the professions. We could survey the history of Western culture and the
information gathered by anthropology in order to find institutions which played a role
like that now performed by schooling. We could, finally, recall the many normative
statements which have been made since the time of Comenius, or even since Quintilian,
and discover which of these the modern school system most closely approaches. But any
of these approaches would oblige us to start with certain assumptions about a relationship
between school and education. To develop a language in which we can speak about
school without such constant recourse to education, I have chosen to begin with
something that might be called a phenomenology of public school. For this purpose I
shall define "school" as the age-specific, teacher-related process requiring full-time
attendance at an obligatory curriculum.

  1. Age School groups people according to age. This grouping rests on three unquestioned
    premises. Children belong in school.

Children learn in school. Children can be taught only in school. I think these unexamined
premises deserve serious questioning. We have grown accustomed to children. We have
decided that they should go to school, do as they are told, and have neither income nor
families of their own. We expect them to know their place and behave like children. We
remember, whether nostalgically or bitterly, a time when we were children, too. We are
expected to tolerate the childish behavior of children. Man-kind, for us, is a species both
afflicted and blessed with the task of caring for children. We forget, however, that our
present concept of "childhood" developed only recently in Western Europe and more

Deschooling Society

Page # 20

recently still in the Americas. [ For parallel histories of modern capitalism and modern
childhood see Philippe Aries, Centuries Of Childhood, Knopf, 1962.]

Childhood as distinct from infancy, adolescence, or youth was unknown to most
historical periods. Some Christian centuries did not even have an eye for its bodily
proportions. Artists depicted the infant as a miniature adult seated on his mother's arm.
Children appeared in Europe along with the pocket watch and the Christian moneylenders
of the Renaissance. Before our century neither the poor nor the rich knew of children's
dress, children's games, or the child's immunity from the law. Childhood belonged to the
bourgeoisie. The worker's child, the peasant's child, and the nobleman's child all dressed
the way their fathers dressed, played the way their fathers played, and were hanged by the
neck as were their fathers. After the discovery of "childhood" by the bourgeoisie all this
changed. Only some churches continued to respect for some time the dignity and maturity
of the young. Until the Second Vatican Council, each child was instructed that a Christian
reaches moral discernment and freedom at the age of seven, and from then on is capable
of committing sins for which he may be punished by an eternity in Hell. Toward the
middle of this century, middle-class parents began to try to spare their children the impact
of this doctrine, and their thinking about children now prevails in the practice of the
Church.

Until the last century, "children" of middle-class parents were made at home with the
help of preceptors and private schools. Only with the advent of industrial society did the
mass production of "childhood" become feasible and come within the reach of the
masses. The school system is a modern phenomenon, as is the childhood it produces.

Since most people today live outside industrial cities, most people today do not
experience childhood. In the Andes you till the soil once you have become "useful."
Before that, you watch the sheep. If you are well nourished, you should be useful by
eleven, and otherwise by twelve. Recently, I was talking to my night watchman, Marcos,
about his eleven-year-old son who works in a barbershop. I noted in Spanish that his son
was still a "ni-o, ” Marcos, surprised, answered with a guileless smile: "Don Ivan, I guess
you're right." Realizing that until my remark the father had thought of Marcos primarily
as his "son," I felt guilty for having drawn the curtain of childhood between two sensible
persons. Of course if I were to tell the New York slum-dweller that his working son is
still a "child," he would show no surprise. He knows quite well that his eleven-year-old
son should be allowed childhood, and resents the fact that he is not. The son of Marcos
has yet to be afflicted with the yearning for childhood; the New Yorker's son feels
deprived.

Most people around the world, then, either do not want or cannot get modem childhood
for their offspring. But it also seems that childhood is a burden to a good number of those
few who are allowed it. Many of them are simply forced to go through it and are not at all
happy playing the child's role. Growing up through childhood means being condemned to
a process of in-human conflict between self-awareness and the role imposed by a society
going through its own school age. Neither Stephen Daedalus nor Alexander Portnoy
enjoyed childhood, and neither, I suspect, did many of us like to be treated as children.

Deschooling Society

Page# 21

If there were no age-specific and obligatory learning institution, "childhood" would go
out of production. The youth of rich nations would be liberated from its destructiveness,
and poor nations would cease attempting to rival the childishness of the rich. If society
were to outgrow its age of childhood, it would have to become livable for the young. The
present disjunction between an adult society which pretends to be humane and a school
environment which mocks reality could no longer be maintained.

The disestablishment of schools could also end the present discrimination against infants,
adults, and the old in favor of children throughout their adolescence and youth. The social
decision to allocate educational resources preferably to those citizens who have outgrown
the extraordinary learning capacity of their first four years and have not arrived at the
height of their self-motivated learning will, in retrospect, probably appear as bizarre.

Institutional wisdom tells us that children need school. Institutional wisdom tells us that
children leam in school. But this institutional wisdom is itself the product of schools
because sound common sense tells us that only children can be taught in school. Only by
segregating human beings in the category of childhood could we ever get them to submit
to the authority of a schoolteacher.

  1. Teachers and Pupils By definition, children are pupils. The demand for the milieu of
    childhood creates an unlimited market for accredited teachers. School is an institution
    built on the axiom that learning is the result of teaching. And institutional wisdom
    continues to accept this axiom, despite overwhelming evidence to the contrary.

We have all learned most of what we know outside school. Pupils do most of their
learning without, and often despite, their teachers. Most tragically, the majority of men
are taught their lesson by schools, even though they never go to school.

Everyone learns how to live outside school. We learn to speak, to think, to love, to feel,
to play, to curse, to politick, and to work without interference from a teacher. Even
children who are under a teacher's care day and night are no exception to the rule.
Orphans, idiots, and schoolteachers' sons leam most of what they learn outside the
"educational" process planned for them. Teachers have made a poor showing in their
attempts at increasing learning among the poor. Poor parents who want their children to
go to school are less concerned about what they will learn than about the certificate and
money they will earn. And middle-class parents commit their children to a teacher's care
to keep them from learning what the poor leam on the streets. Increasingly educational
research demonstrates that children leam most of what teachers pretend to teach them
from peer groups, from comics, from chance observations, and above all from mere
participation in the ritual of school. Teachers, more often than not, obstruct such learning
of subject matters as goes on in school.

Half of the people in our world never set foot in school. They have no contact with
teachers, and they are deprived of the privilege of becoming dropouts. Yet they leam
quite effectively the message which school teaches: that they should have school, and
more and more of it. School instructs them in their own inferiority through the tax

Deschooling Society

Page # 22

collector who makes them pay for it, or through the demagogue who raises their
expectations of it, or through their children once the latter are hooked on it. So the poor
are robbed of their self-respect by subscribing to a creed that grants salvation only
through the school. At least the Church gave them a chance to repent at the hour of death.
School leaves them with the expectation (a counterfeit hope) that their grandchildren will
make it. That expectation is of course still more learning which comes from school but
not from teachers.

Pupils have never credited teachers for most of their learning. Bright and dull alike have
always relied on rote, reading, and wit to pass their exams, motivated by the stick or by
the carrot of a desired career.

Adults tend to romanticize their schooling. In retrospect, they attribute their learning to
the teacher whose patience they learned to admire. But the same adults would worry
about the mental health of a child who rushed home to tell them what he learned from his
every teacher.

Schools create jobs for schoolteachers, no matter what their pupils learn from them.

  1. Full-Time Attendance Every month I see another list of proposals made by some U.S.
    industry to AID, suggesting the replacement of Latin-American "classroom practitioners"
    either by disciplined systems administrators or just by TV. In the United States teaching
    as a team enterprise of educational researchers, designers, and technicians is gaining
    acceptance. But, no matter whether the teacher is a schoolmarm or a team of men in
    white coats, and no matter whether they succeed in teaching the subject matter listed in
    the catalogue or whether they fail, the professional teacher creates a sacred milieu.

Uncertainty about the future of professional teaching puts the classroom into jeopardy.
Were educational professionals to specialize in promoting learning, they would have to
abandon a system which calls for between 750 and 1,000 gatherings a year. But of course
teachers do a lot more. The institutional wisdom of schools tells parents, pupils, and
educators that the teacher, if he is to teach, must exercise his authority in a sacred
precinct. This is true even for teachers whose pupils spend most of their school time in a
classroom without walls.

School, by its very nature, tends to make a total claim on the time and energies of its
participants. This, in turn, makes the teacher into custodian, preacher, and therapist.

In each of these three roles the teacher bases his authority on a different claim.

Th eteacher-as-custodian acts as a master of ceremonies, who guides his pupils through a
drawn-out labyrinthine ritual. He arbitrates the observance of rules and administers the
intricate rubrics of initiation to life. At his best, he sets the stage for the acquisition of
some skill as schoolmasters always have. Without illusions of producing any profound
learning, he drills his pupils in some basic routines.

Deschooling Society

Page # 23

The teacher-as-moralist substitutes for parents, God, or the state. He indoctrinates the
pupil about what is right or wrong, not only in school but also in society at large. He
stands in loco parentis for each one and thus ensures that all feel themselves children of
the same state.

The teacher-as-therapist feels authorized to delve into the personal life of his pupil in
order to help him grow as a person. When this function is exercised by a custodian and
preacher, it usually means that he persuades the pupil to submit to a domestication of his
vision of truth and his sense of what is right.

The claim that a liberal society can be founded on the modern school is paradoxical. The
safeguards of individual freedom are all canceled in the dealings of a teacher with his
pupil. When the schoolteacher fuses in his person the functions of judge, ideologue, and
doctor, the fundamental style of society is perverted by the very process which should
prepare for life. A teacher who combines these three powers contributes to the warping of
the child much more than the laws which establish his legal or economic minority, or
restrict his right to free assembly or abode.

Teachers are by no means the only professionals who offer therapy. Psychiatrists,
guidance counselors, and job counselors, even lawyers, help their clients to decide, to
develop their personalities, and to learn. Yet common sense tells the client that such
professionals should abstain from imposing their opinion of what is right or wrong, or
from forcing anyone to follow their advice. Schoolteachers and ministers are the only
professionals who feel entitled to pry into the private affairs of their clients at the same
time as they preach to a captive audience.

Children are protected by neither the First nor the Fifth Amendment when they stand
before that secular priest, the teacher. The child must confront a man who wears an
invisible triple crown, like the papal tiara, the symbol of triple authority combined in one
person. For the child, the teacher pontificates as pastor, prophet, and priest-he is at once
guide, teacher, and administrator of a sacred ritual. He combines the claims of medieval
popes in a society constituted under the guarantee that these claims shall never be
exercised together by one established and obligatory institution— church or state.

Defining children as full-time pupils permits the teacher to exercise a kind of power over
their persons which is much less limited by constitutional and consuetudinal restrictions
than the power wielded by the guardians of other social enclaves. Their chronological age
disqualifies children from safeguards which are routine for adults in a modern asylum-
madhouse, monastery, or jail.

Under the authoritative eye of the teacher, several orders of value collapse into one. The
distinctions between morality, legal, ity, and personal worth are blurred and eventually
eliminated. Each transgression is made to be felt as a multiple offense. The offender is
expected to feel that he has broken a rule, that he has behaved immorally, and that he has
let himself down. A pupil who adroitly obtains assistance on an exam is told that he is an
outlaw, morally corrupt, and personally worthless.

Deschooling Society

Page # 24

Classroom attendance removes children from the everyday world of Western culture and
plunges them into an environment far more primitive, magical, and deadly serious.

School could not create such an enclave within which the rules of ordinary reality are
suspended, unless it physically incarcerated the young during many successive years on
sacred territory. The attendance rule makes it possible for the schoolroom to serve as a
magic womb, from which the child is delivered periodically at the school days and school
year's completion until he is finally expelled into adult life. Neither universal extended
childhood nor the smothering atmosphere of the classroom could exist without schools.
Yet schools, as compulsory channels for learning, could exist without either and be more
repressive and destructive than anything we have come to know. To understand what it
means to deschool society, and not just to reform the educational establishment, we must
now focus on the hidden curriculum of schooling. We are not concerned here, directly,
with the hidden curriculum of the ghetto streets which brands the poor or with the hidden
curriculum of the drawing room which benefits the rich. We are rather concerned to call
attention to the fact that the ceremonial or ritual of schooling itself constitutes such a
hidden curriculum. Even the best of teachers cannot entirely protect his pupils from it.
Inevitably, this hidden curriculum of schooling adds prejudice and guilt to the
discrimination which a society practices against some of its members and compounds the
privilege of others with a new title to condescend to the majority. Just as inevitably, this
hidden curriculum serves as a ritual of initiation into a growth-oriented consumer society
for rich and poor alike.

Deschooling Society

Page # 25

3

Ritualization of Progress

The university graduate has been schooled for selective service among the rich of the
world. Whatever his or her claims of solidarity with the Third World, each American
college graduate has had an education costing an amount five times greater than the
median life income of half of humanity. A Latin American student is introduced to this
exclusive fraternity by having at least 350 times as much public money spent on his
education as on that of his fellow citizens of median income. With very rare exceptions,
the university graduate from a poor country feels more comfortable with his North
American and European colleagues than with his nonschooled compatriots, and all
students are academically processed to be happy only in the company of fellow
consumers of the products of the educational machine.

The modern university confers the privilege of dissent on those who have been tested and
classified as potential money-makers or power-holders. No one is given tax funds for the
leisure in which to educate himself or the right to educate others unless at the same time
he can also be certified for achievement. Schools select for each successive level those
who have, at earlier stages in the game, proved themselves good risks for the established
order. Having a monopoly on both the resources for learning and the investiture of social
roles, the university coopts the discoverer and the potential dissenter. A degree always
leaves its indelible price tag on the curriculum of its consumer. Certified college
graduates fit only into a world which puts a price tag on their heads, thereby giving them
the power to define the level of expectations in their society. In each country the amount
of consumption by the college graduate sets the standard for all others; if they would be
civilized people on or off the job, they will aspire to the style of life of college graduates.

The university thus has the effect of imposing consumer standards at work and at home,
and it does so in every part of the world and under every political system. The fewer
university graduates there are in a country, the more their cultivated demands are taken as
models by the rest of the population. The gap between the consumption of the university
graduate and that of the average citizen is even wider in Russia, China, and Algeria than
in the United States. Cars, airplane trips, and tape recorders confer more visible
distinction in a socialist country, where only a degree, and not just money, can procure
them.

The ability of the university to fix consumer goals is something new. In many countries
the university acquired this power only in the sixties, as the delusion of equal access to

Deschooling Society

Page # 26

public education began to spread. Before that the university protected an individual's
freedom of speech, but did not automatically convert his knowledge into wealth. To be a
scholar in the Middle Ages meant to be poor, even a beggar. By virtue of his calling, the
medieval scholar learned Latin, became an outsider worthy of the scorn as well as the
esteem of peasant and prince, burgher and cleric. To get ahead in the world, the scholastic
first had to enter it by joining the civil service, preferably that of the Church. The old
university was a liberated zone for discovery and the discussion of ideas both new and
old. Masters and students gathered to read the texts of other masters, now long dead, and
the living words of the dead masters gave new perspective to the fallacies of the present
day. The university was then a community of academic quest and endemic unrest.

In the modem multiversity this community has fled to the fringes, where it meets in a
pad, a professor's office, or the chaplain's quarters. The structural purpose of the modem
university has little to do with the traditional quest. Since Gutenberg, the exchange of
disciplined, critical inquiry has, for the most part, moved from the "chair" into print. The
modern university has forfeited its chance to provide a simple setting for encounters
which are both autonomous and anarchic, focused yet unplanned and ebullient, and has
chosen instead to manage the process by which so-called research and instruction are
produced.

The American university, since Sputnik, has been trying to catch up with the body count
of Soviet graduates. Now the Germans are abandoning their academic tradition and are
building "campuses" in order to catch up with the Americans. During the present decade
they want to increase their expenditure for grammar and high schools from 14 to 59
billion DM, and more than triple expenditures for higher learning. The French propose by
1980 to raise to 10 percent of their GNP the amount spent on schools, and the Ford
Foundation has been pushing poor countries in Latin America to raise per capita expenses
for "respect-able" graduates toward North American levels. Students see their studies as
the investment with the highest monetary return, and nations see them as a key factor in
development.

For the majority who primarily seek a college degree, the university has lost no prestige,
but since 1968 it has visibly lost standing among its believers. Students refuse to prepare
for war, pollution, and the perpetuation of prejudice. Teachers assist them in their
challenge to the legitimacy of the government, its foreign policy, education, and the
American way of life. More than a few reject degrees and prepare for a life in a
counterculture, outside the certified society. They seem to choose the way of medieval
Fraticelli and Alumbrados of the Reformation, the hippies and dropouts of their day.
Others recognize the monopoly of the schools over the resources which they need to
build a countersociety. They seek support from each other to live with integrity while
submitting to the academic ritual. They form, so to speak, hotbeds of heresy right within
the hierarchy.

Large parts of the general population, however, regard the modern mystic and the modem
heresiarch with alarm. They threaten the consumer economy, democratic privilege, and
the self-image of America. But they cannot be wished away. Fewer and fewer can be

Deschooling Society

Page# 27

reconverted by patience or coopted by subtlety for instance, by appointing them to teach
their heresy. Hence the search for means which would make it possible either to get rid of
dissident individuals or to reduce the importance of the university which serves them as a
base for protest.

The students and faculty who question the legitimacy of the university, and do so at high
personal cost, certainly do not feel that they are setting consumer standards or abetting a
production system. Those who have founded such groups as the Committee of Concerned
Asian Scholars and the North American Congress on Latin America (NACLA) have been
among the most effective in changing radically the perceptions of the realities of foreign
countries for millions of young people. Still others have tried to formulate Marxian
interpretations of American society or have been among those responsible for the
flowering of communes. Their achievements add new strength to the argument that the
existence of the university is necessary to guarantee continued social criticism.

There is no question that at present the university offers a unique combination of
circumstances which allows some of its members to criticize the whole of society. It
provides time, mobility, access to peers and information, and a certain impunity-
privileges not equally available to other segments of the population. But the university
provides this freedom only to those who have already been deeply initiated into the
consumer society and into the need for some kind of obligatory public schooling.

The school system today performs the threefold function common to powerful churches
throughout history. It is simultaneously the repository of society's myth, the
institutionalization of that myth's contradictions, and the locus of the ritual which
reproduces and veils the disparities between myth and reality. Today the school system,
and especially the university, provides ample opportunity for criticism of the myth and
for rebellion against its institutional perversions. But the ritual which demands tolerance
of the fundamental contradictions between myth and institution still goes largely
unchallenged, for neither ideological criticism nor social action can bring about a new
society. Only disenchantment with and detachment from the central social ritual and
reform of that ritual can bring about radical change.

The American university has become the final stage of the most all encompassing
initiation rite the world has ever known. No society in history has been able to survive
without ritual or myth, but ours is the first which has needed such a dull, protracted,
destructive, and expensive initiation into its myth. The contemporary world civilization is
also the first one which has found it necessary to rationalize its fundamental initiation
ritual in the name of education. We cannot begin a reform of education unless we first
understand that neither individual learning nor social equality can be enhanced by the
ritual of schooling. We cannot go beyond the consumer society unless we first understand
that obligatory public schools inevitably reproduce such a society, no matter what is
taught in them.

The project of demythologizing which I propose cannot be limited to the university alone.
Any attempt to reform the university without attending to the system of which it is an

Deschooling Society

Page # 28

integral part is like trying to do urban renewal in New York City from the twelfth story
up. Most current college-level reform looks like the building of high-rise slums. Only a
generation which grows up without obligatory schools will be able to recreate the
university.

The Myth of Institutionalized Values

School initiates, too, the Myth of Unending Consumption. This modem myth is
grounded in the belief that process inevitably produces something of value and, therefore,
production necessarily produces demand. School teaches us that instruction produces
learning. The existence of schools produces the demand for schooling. Once we have
learned to need school, all our activities tend to take the shape of client relationships to
other specialized institutions. Once the self-taught man or woman has been discredited,
all nonprofessional activity is rendered suspect. In school we are taught that valuable
learning is the result of attendance; that the value of learning increases with the amount
of input; and, finally, that this value can be measured and documented by grades and
certificates.

In fact, learning is the human activity which least needs manipulation by others. Most
learning is not the result of instruction. It is rather the result of unhampered participation
in a meaningful setting. Most people learn best by being "with it," yet school makes them
identify their personal, cognitive growth with elaborate planning and manipulation.

Once a man or woman has accepted the need for school, he or she is easy prey for other
institutions. Once young people have allowed their imaginations to be formed by
curricular instruction, they are conditioned to institutional planning of every sort.
"Instruction" smothers the horizon of their imaginations. They cannot be betrayed, but
only short-changed, because they have been taught to substitute expectations for hope.
They will no longer be surprised, for good or ill, by other people, because they have been
taught what to expect from every other person who has been taught as they were. This is
true in the case of another person or in the case of a machine.

This transfer of responsibility from self to institution guarantees social regression,
especially once it has been accepted as an obligation. So rebels against Alma Mater often
"make it" into her faculty instead of growing into the courage to infect others with their
personal teaching and to assume responsibility for the results. This suggests the
possibility of a new Oedipus story-Oedipus the Teacher, who "makes" his mother in
order to engender children with her. The man addicted to being taught seeks his security
in compulsive teaching. The woman who experiences her knowledge as the result of a
process wants to reproduce it in others.

The Myth of Measurement of Values

The institutionalized values school instills are quantified ones. School initiates young
people into a world where everything can be measured, including their imaginations, and,
indeed, man himself.

Deschooling Society

Page # 29

But personal growth is not a measurable entity. It is growth in disciplined dissidence,
which cannot be measured against any rod, or any curriculum, nor compared to someone
else's achievement. In such learning one can emulate others only in imaginative
endeavor, and follow in their footsteps rather than mimic their gait. The learning I prize is
immeasurable re-creation.

School pretends to break learning up into subject "matters," to build into the pupil a
curriculum made of these prefabricated blocks, and to gauge the result on an international
scale. People who submit to the standard of others for the measure of their own personal
growth soon apply the same ruler to themselves. They no longer have to be put in their
place, but put themselves into their assigned slots, squeeze themselves into the niche
which they have been taught to seek, and, in the very process, put their fellows into their
places, too, until everybody and everything fits.

People who have been schooled down to size let unmeasured experience slip out of their
hands. To them, what cannot be measured becomes secondary, threatening. They do not
have to be robbed of their creativity. Under instruction, they have unlearned to "do" their
thing or "be" themselves, and value only what has been made or could be made.

Once people have the idea schooled into them that values can be produced and measured,
they tend to accept all kinds of rank' ings. There is a scale for the development of nations,
another for the intelligence of babies, and even progress toward peace can be calculated
according to body count. In a schooled world the road to happiness is paved with a
consumer's index.

The Myth of Packaging Values

School sells curriculum— a bundle of goods made according to the same process and
having the same structure as other merchandise. Curriculum production for most schools
begins with allegedly scientific research, on whose basis educational engineers predict
future demand and tools for the assembly line, within the limits set by budgets and
taboos. The distributor-teacher delivers the finished product to the consumer pupil, whose
reactions are carefully studied and charted to provide research data for the preparation of
the next model, which may be "ungraded," "student-designed," "team-taught," "visually-
aided," or "issue-centered."

The result of the curriculum production process looks like any other modern staple. It is a
bundle of planned meanings, a package of values, a commodity whose "balanced appeal"
makes it marketable to a sufficiently large number to justify the cost of production.
Consumer-pupils are taught to make their desires conform to marketable values. Thus
they are made to feel guilty if they do not behave according to the predictions of
consumer research by getting the grades and certificates that will place them in the job
category they have been led to expect.

Educators can justify more expensive curricula on the basis of their observation that
learning difficulties rise proportionately with the cost of the curriculum. This is an

Deschooling Society

Page # 30

application of Parkinson's Law that work expands with the resources available to do it.
This law can be verified on all levels of school: for instance, reading difficulties have
been a major issue in French schools only since their per capita expenditures have
approached U.S. levels of 1950-when reading difficulties became a major issue in U.S.
schools.

In fact, healthy students often redouble their resistance to teaching as they find
themselves more comprehensively manipulated. This resistance is due not to the
authoritarian style of a public school or the seductive style of some free schools, but to
the fundamental approach common to all schools-the idea that one person's judgment
should determine what and when another person must learn.

The Myth of Self-Perpetuating Progress

Even when accompanied by declining returns in learning, paradoxically, rising per capita
instructional costs increase the value of the pupil in his or her own eyes and on the
market. At almost any cost, school pushes the pupil up to the level of competitive
curricular consumption, into progress to ever higher levels. Expenditures to motivate the
student to stay on in school skyrocket as he climbs the pyramid. On higher levels they are
disguised as new football stadiums, chapels, or programs called International Education.
If it teaches nothing else, school teaches the value of escalation: the value of the
American way of doing things.

The Vietnam war fits the logic of the moment. Its success has been measured by the
numbers of persons effectively treated by cheap bullets delivered at immense cost, and
this brutal calculus is unashamedly called "body count." Just as business is business, the
never-ending accumulation of money, so war is killing, the never-ending accumulation of
dead bodies. In like manner, education is schooling, and this open-ended process is
counted in pupil-hours. The various processes are irreversible and self-justifying. By
economic standards the country gets richer and richer. By death-accounting standards the
nation goes on winning its war forever. And by school standards the population becomes
increasingly educated.

School programs hunger for progressive intake of instruction, but even if the hunger leads
to steady absorption, it never yields the joy of knowing something to one's satisfaction.
Each subject comes packaged with the instruction to go on consuming one "offering"
after another, and last year's wrapping is always obsolete for this year's consumer. The
textbook racket builds on this demand. Educational reformers promise each new
generation the latest and the best, and the public is schooled into demanding what they
offer. Both the dropout who is forever reminded of what he missed and the graduate who
is made to feel inferior to the new breed of student know exactly where they stand in the
ritual of rising deceptions and continue to support a society which euphemistically calls
the widening frustration gap a "revolution of rising expectations."

Deschooling Society

Page #31

But growth conceived as open-ended consumption-eternal progress-can never lead to
maturity. Commitment to unlimited quantitative increase vitiates the possibility of
organic development.

Ritual Game and the New World Religion

The school leaving age in developed nations outpaces the rise in life expectancy. The
two curves will intersect in a decade and create a problem for Jessica Mitford and
professionals concerned with "terminal education." I am reminded of the late Middle
Ages, when the demand for Church services outgrew a lifetime, and "Purgatory" was
created to purify souls under the pope's control before they could enter eternal peace.
Logically, this led first to a trade in indulgences and then to an attempt at Reformation.
The Myth of Unending Consumption now takes the place of belief in life everlasting.

Arnold Toynbee has pointed out that the decadence of a great culture is usually
accompanied by the rise of a new World Church which extends hope to the domestic
proletariat while serving the needs of a new warrior class. School seems eminently suited
to be the World Church of our decaying culture. No institution could better veil from its
participants the deep discrepancy between social principles and social reality in today's
world. Secular, scientific, and death-denying, it is of a piece with the modern mood. Its
classical, critical veneer makes it appear pluralist if not antireligious. Its curriculum both
defines science and is itself defined by so-called scientific research. No one completes
school— yet. It never closes its doors on anyone without first offering him one more
chance: at remedial, adult, and continuing education.

School serves as an effective creator and sustainer of social myth because of its structure
as a ritual game of graded promotions. Introduction into this gambling ritual is much
more important than what or how something is taught. It is the game itself that schools,
that gets into the blood and becomes a habit. A whole society is initiated into the Myth of
Unending Consumption of services. This happens to the degree that token participation in
the open-ended ritual is made compulsory and compulsive everywhere. School directs
ritual rivalry into an international game which obliges competitors to blame the world's
ills on those who cannot or will not play. School is a ritual of initiation which introduces
the neophyte to the sacred race of progressive consumption, a ritual of propitiation whose
academic priests mediate between the faithful and the gods of privilege and power, a
ritual of expiation which sacrifices its dropouts, branding them as scapegoats of
underdevelopment .

Even those who spend at best a few years in school-and this is the overwhelming
majority in Latin America, Asia, and Africa-leam to feel guilty because of their
underconsumption of schooling. In Mexico six grades of school are legally obligatory.
Children bom into the lower economic third have only two chances in three to make it
into the first grade. If they make it, they have four chances in one hundred to finish
obligatory schooling by the sixth grade. If they are born into the middle third group, their
chances increase to twelve out of a hundred. With these rules, Mexico is more successful

Deschooling Society

Page # 32

than most of the other twenty-five Latin American republics in providing public
education.

Everywhere, all children know that they were given a chance, albeit an unequal one, in an
obligatory lottery, and the presumed equality of the international standard now
compounds their original poverty with the self-inflicted discrimination accepted by the
dropout. They have been schooled to the belief in rising expectations and can now
rationalize their growing frustration outside school by accepting their rejection from
scholastic grace. They are excluded from Heaven because, once baptized, they did not go
to church. Bom in original sin, they are baptized into first grade, but go to Gehenna
(which in Hebrew means "slum") because of their personal faults. As Max Weber traced
the social effects of the belief that salvation belonged to those who accumulated wealth,
we can now observe that grace is reserved for those who accumulate years in school.

The Coming Kingdom: The Universalization of Expectations

School combines the expectations of the consumer expressed in its claims with the
beliefs of the producer expressed in its ritual, It is a liturgical expression of a world- wide
"cargo cult," reminiscent of the cults which swept Melanesia in the forties, which injected
cultists with the belief that if they but put on a black tie over their naked torsos, Jesus
would arrive in a steamer bearing an icebox, a pair of trousers, and a sewing machine for
each believer.

School fuses the growth in humiliating dependence on a master with the growth in the
futile sense of omnipotence that is so typical of the pupil who wants to go out and teach
all nations to save themselves. The ritual is tailored to the stern work habits of the
hardhats, and its purpose is to celebrate the myth of an earthly paradise of never-ending
consumption, which is the only hope for the wretched and dispossessed.

Epidemics of insatiable this-worldly expectations have occurred throughout history,
especially among colonized and marginal groups in all cultures. Jews in the Roman
Empire had their Essenes and Jewish messiahs, serfs in the Reformation their Thomas
MYnzer, dispossessed Indians from Paraguay to Dakota their infectious dancers. These
sects were always led by a prophet, and limited their promises to a chosen few. The
school-induced expectation of the kingdom, on the other hand, is impersonal rather than
prophetic, and universal rather than local. Man has become the engineer of his own
messiah and promises the unlimited rewards of science to those who submit to
progressive engineering for his reign.

The New Alienation

School is not only the New World Religion. It is also the world's fastest-growing labor
market. The engineering of consumers has become the economy's principal growth
sector. As production costs decrease in rich nations, there is an increasing concentration
of both capital and labor in the vast enterprise of equipping man for disciplined
consumption. During the past decade capital investments directly related to the school

Deschooling Society

Page # 33

system rose even faster than expenditures for defense. Disarmament would only
accelerate the process by which the learning industry moves to the center of the national
economy. School gives unlimited opportunity for legitimated waste, so long as its
destructiveness goes unrecognized and the cost of palliatives goes up.

If we add those engaged in full-time teaching to those in full-time attendance, we realize
that this so-called superstructure has become society's major employer. In the United
States sixty-two million people are in school and eighty million at work elsewhere. This
is often forgotten by neo-Marxist analysts who say that the process of deschooling must
be postponed or bracketed until other disorders, traditionally understood as more
fundamental, are corrected by an economic and political revolution. Only if school is
understood as an industry can revolutionary strategy be planned realistically. For Marx,
the cost of producing demands for commodities was barely significant. Today most
human labor is engaged in the production of demands that can be satisfied by industry
which makes intensive use of capital. Most of this is done in school.

Alienation, in the traditional scheme, was a direct consequence of work's becoming
wage-labor which deprived man of the opportunity to create and be recreated. Now
young people are prealienated by schools that isolate them while they pretend to be both
producers and consumers of their own knowledge, which is conceived of as a commodity
put on the market in school. School makes alienation preparatory to life, thus depriving
education of reality and work of creativity. School prepares for the alienating
institutionalization of life by teaching the need to be taught. Once this lesson is learned,
people lose their incentive to grow in independence; they no longer find relatedness
attractive, and close themselves off to the surprises which life offers when it is not
predetermined by institutional definition. And school directly or indirectly employs a
major portion of the population. School either keeps people for life or makes sure that
they will fit into some institution.

The New World Church is the knowledge industry, both purveyor of opium and the
workbench during an increasing number of the years of an individual's life. Deschooling
is, therefore, at the root of any movement for human liberation.

The Revolutionary Potential of Deschooling

Of course, school is not, by any means, the only modern institution which has as its
primary purpose the shaping of man's vision of reality. The hidden curriculum of family
life, draft, health care, so-called professionalism, or of the media play an important part in
the institutional manipulation of man's world-vision, language, and demands. But school
enslaves more profoundly and more systematically, since only school is credited with the
principal function of forming critical judgment, and, paradoxically, tries to do so by
making learning about oneself, about others, and about nature depend on a prepackaged
process. School touches us so intimately that none of us can expect to be liberated from it
by something else.

Deschooling Society

Page # 34

Many self-styled revolutionaries are victims of school. They see even "liberation" as the
product of an institutional process. Only liberating oneself from school will dispel such
illusions. The discovery that most learning requires no teaching can be neither
manipulated nor planned. Each of us is personally responsible for his or her own
deschooling, and only we have the power to do it. No one can be excused if he fails to
liberate himself from schooling. People could not free themselves from the Crown until at
least some of them had freed themselves from the established Church. They cannot free
themselves from progressive consumption until they free themselves from obligatory
school.

We are all involved in schooling, from both the side of production and that of
consumption. We are superstitiously convinced that good learning can and should be
produced in us-and that we can produce it in others. Our attempt to withdraw from the
concept of school will reveal the resistance we find in ourselves when we try to renounce
limitless consumption and the pervasive presumption that others can be manipulated for
their own good. No one is fully exempt from the exploitation of others in the schooling
process.

School is both the largest and the most anonymous employer of all. Indeed, the school is
the best example of a new kind of enterprise, succeeding the guild, the factory, and the
corporation. The multinational corporations which have dominated the economy are now
being complemented, and may one day be replaced, by supemationally planned service
agencies. These enterprises present their services in ways that make all men feel obliged
to consume them. They are internationally standardized, redefining the value of their
services periodically and everywhere at approximately the same rhythm.

"Transportation" relying on new cars and superhighways serves the same institutionally
packaged need for comfort, prestige, speed, and gadgetry, whether its components are
produced by the state or not. The apparatus of "medical care" defines a peculiar kind of
health, whether the service is paid for by the state or by the individual. Graded promotion
in order to obtain diplomas fits the student for a place on the same international pyramid
of qualified manpower, no matter who directs the school.

In all these cases employment is a hidden benefit: the driver of a private automobile, the
patient who submits to hospitalization, or the pupil in the schoolroom must now be seen
as part of a new class of "employees." A liberation movement which starts in school, and
yet is grounded in the awareness of teachers and pupils as simultaneously exploiters and
exploited, could foreshadow the revolutionary strategies of the future; for a radical
program of deschooling could train youth in the new style of revolution needed to
challenge a social system featuring obligatory "health," "wealth," and "security."

The risks of a revolt against school are unforeseeable, but they are not as horrible as those
of a revolution starting in any other major institution. School is not yet organized for self-
protection as effectively as a nation-state, or even a large corporation. Liberation from the
grip of schools could be bloodless. The weapons of the truant officer and his allies in the
courts and employment agencies might take very cruel measures against the individual

Deschooling Society

Page # 35

offender, especially if he or she were poor, but they might turn out to be powerless
against the surge of a mass movement.

School has become a social problem; it is being attacked on all sides, and citizens and
their governments sponsor unconventional experiments all over the world. They resort to
unusual statistical devices in order to keep faith and save face. The mood among some
educators is much like the mood among Catholic bishops after the Vatican Council. The
curricula of so-called "free schools" resemble the liturgies of folk and rock masses. The
demands of high-school students to have a say in choosing their teachers are as strident as
those of parishioners demanding to select their pastors. But the stakes for society are
much higher if a significant minority loses its faith in schooling. This would endanger the
survival not only of the economic order built on the coproduction of goods and demands,
but equally of the political order built on the nation-state into which students are
delivered by the school.

Our options are clear enough. Either we continue to believe that institutionalized learning
is a product which justifies unlimited investment or we rediscover that legislation and
planning and investment, if they have any place in formal education, should be used
mostly to tear down the barriers that now impede opportunities for learning, which can
only be a personal activity.

If we do not challenge the assumption that valuable knowledge is a commodity which
under certain circumstances may be forced into the consumer, society will be
increasingly dominated by sinister pseudo schools and totalitarian managers of
information. Pedagogical therapists will drug their pupils more in order to teach them
better, and students will drug themselves more to gain relief from the pressures of
teachers and the race for certificates. Increasingly larger numbers of bureaucrats will
presume to pose as teachers. The language of the schoolman has already been coopted by
the adman. Now the general and the policeman try to dignify their professions by
masquerading as educators. In a schooled society, warmaking and civil repression find an
educational rationale. Pedagogical warfare in the style of Vietnam will be increasingly
justified as the only way of teaching people the superior value of unending progress.

Repression will be seen as a missionary effort to hasten the coming of the mechanical
Messiah. More and more countries will resort to the pedagogical torture already
implemented in Brazil and Greece. This pedagogical torture is not used to extract
information or to satisfy the psychic needs of sadists. It relies on random terror to break
the integrity of an entire population and make it plastic material for the teachings
invented by technocrats. The totally destructive and constantly progressive nature of
obligatory instruction will fulfill its ultimate logic unless we begin to liberate ourselves
right now from our pedagogical hubris, our belief that man can do what God cannot,
namely, manipulate others for their own salvation.

Many people are just awakening to the inexorable destruction which present production
trends imply for the environment, but individuals have only very limited power to change
these trends. The manipulation of men and women begun in school has also reached a

Deschooling Society

Page # 36

point of no return, and most people are still unaware of it. They still encourage school
reform, as Henry Ford II proposes less poisonous automobiles.

Daniel Bell says that our epoch is characterized by an extreme disjunction between
cultural and social structures, the one being devoted to apocalyptic attitudes, the other to
technocratic decision-making. This is certainly true for many educational reformers, who
feel impelled to condemn almost everything which characterizes modern schools-and at
the same time propose new schools.

In his The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Thomas Kuhn argues that such dissonance
inevitably precedes the emergence of a new cognitive paradigm. The facts reported by
those who observed free fall, by those who returned from the other side of the earth, and
by those who used the new telescope did not fit the Ptolemaic world view. Quite
suddenly, the Newtonian paradigm was accepted. The dissonance which characterizes
many of the young today is not so much cognitive as a matter of attitudes— a feeling about
what a tolerable society cannot be like. What is surprising about this dissonance is the
ability of a very large number of people to tolerate it.

The capacity to pursue incongruous goals requires an explanation. According to Max
Gluckman, all societies have procedures to hide such dissonances from their members.

He suggests that this is the purpose of ritual. Rituals can hide from their participants even
discrepancies and conflicts between social principle and social organization. As long as
an individual is not explicitly conscious of the ritual character of the process through
which he was initiated to the forces which shape his cosmos, he cannot break the spell
and shape a new cosmos. As long as we are not aware of the ritual through which school
shapes the progressive consumer— the economy's major resource— we cannot break the
spell of this economy and shape a new one.

Deschooling Society

Page# 37

4

Institutional Spectrum

Most utopian schemes and futuristic scenarios call for new and costly technologies,
which would have to be sold to rich and poor nations alike. Herman Kahn has found
pupils in Venezuela, Argentina, and Colombia. The pipe dreams of Sergio Bernardes for
his Brazil of the year 2000 sparkle with more new machinery than is now possessed by
the United States, which by then will be weighted down with the antiquated missile sites,
jetports, and cities of the sixties and seventies. Futurists inspired by Buckminster Fuller
would depend on cheaper and more exotic devices. They count on the acceptance of a
new but possible technology that would apparently allow us to make more with less-
lightweight monorails rather than supersonic transport; vertical living rather than
horizontal sprawling. All of today's futuristic planners seek to make economically
feasible what is technically possible while refusing to face the inevitable social
consequence: the increased craving of all men for goods and services that will remain the
privilege of a few.

I believe that a desirable future depends on our deliberately choosing a life of action over
a life of consumption, on our engendering a life style which will enable us to be
spontaneous, independent, yet related to each other, rather than maintaining a life style
which only allows us to make and unmake, produce and consume-a style of life which is
merely a way station on the road to the depletion and pollution of the environment. The
future depends more upon our choice of institutions which support a life of action than on
our developing new ideologies and technologies. We need a set of criteria which will
permit us to recognize those institutions which support personal growth rather than
addiction, as well as the will to invest our techno-logical resources preferentially in such
institutions of growth.

The choice is between two radically opposed institutional types, both of which are
exemplified in certain existing institutions, although one type so characterizes the
contemporary period, as to almost define it. This dominant type I would propose to call
the manipulative institution. The other type also exists, but only precariously. The
institutions which fit it are humbler and less noticeable; yet I take them as models for a
more desirable future. I call them "convivial" and suggest placing them at the left of an
institutional spectrum, both to show that there are institutions which fall between the

Deschooling Society

Page # 38

extremes and to illustrate how historical institutions can change color as they shift from
facilitating activity to organizing production.

Generally, such a spectrum, moving from left to right, has been used to characterize men
and their ideologies, not our social institutions and their styles. This categorization of
men, whether as individuals or in groups, often generates more heat than light. Weighty
objections can be raised against using an ordinary convention in an unusual fashion, but
by doing so I hope to shift the terms of the discussion from a sterile to a fertile plane. It
will become evident that men of the left are not always characterized by their opposition
to the manipulative institutions, which I locate to the right on the spectrum.

The most influential modern institutions crowd up at the right of the spectrum. Law
enforcement has moved there, as it has shifted from the hands of the sheriff to those of
the FBI and the Pentagon. Modern warfare has become a highly professional enterprise
whose business is killing. It has reached the point where its efficiency is measured in
body counts. Its peace-keeping potential depends on its ability to convince friend and foe
of the nation's unlimited death-dealing power. Modern bullets and chemicals are so
effective that a few cents' worth, properly delivered to the intended "client," unfailingly
kill or maim. But delivery costs rise vertiginously; the cost of a dead Vietnamese went
from $360,000 in 1967 to $450,000 in 1969. Only economies on a scale approaching race
suicide would render modem warfare economically efficient. The boomerang effect in
war is becoming more obvious: the higher the body count of dead Vietnamese, the more
enemies the United States acquires around the world; likewise, the more the United States
must spend to create another manipulative institution— cynically dubbed "pacification" in
a futile effort to absorb the side effects of war.

At this same extreme on the spectrum we also find social agencies which specialize in the
manipulation of their clients. Like the military, they tend to develop effects contrary to
their aims as the scope of their operations increases. These social institutions are equally
counterproductive, but less obviously so. Many assume a therapeutic and compassionate
image to mask this paradoxical effect. For example, jails, up until two centuries ago,
served as a means of detaining men until they were sentenced, maimed, killed, or exiled,
and were sometimes deliberately used as a form of torture. Only recently have we begun
to claim that locking people up in cages will have a beneficial effect on their character
and behavior. Now quite a few people are beginning to understand that jail increases both
the quality and the quantity of criminals, that, in fact, it often creates them out of mere
nonconformists. Far fewer people, however, seem to understand that mental hospitals,
nursing homes, and orphan asylums do much the same thing. These institutions provide
their clients with the destructive self-image of the psychotic, the overaged, or the waif,
and provide a rationale for the existence of entire professions, just as jails produce
income for wardens. Membership in the institutions found at this extreme of the spectrum
is achieved in two ways, both coercive: by forced commitment or by selective service.

At the opposite extreme of the spectrum lie institutions distinguished by spontaneous use-
the "convivial" institutions. Telephone link-ups, subway lines, mail routes, public
markets and exchanges do not require hard or soft sells to induce their clients to use

Deschooling Society

Page # 39

them. Sewage systems, drinking water, parks, and side-walks are institutions men use
without having to be institutionally convinced that it is to their advantage to do so. Of
course, all institutions require some regulation. But the opera, tion of institutions which
exist to be used rather than to produce something requires rules of an entirely different
nature from those required by treatment-institutions, which are manipulative. The rules
which govern institutions for use have mainly the purpose of avoiding abuses which
would frustrate their general accessibility. Sidewalks must be kept free of obstructions,
the industrial use of drinking water must be held within limits, and ball playing must be
restricted to special areas within a park. At present we need legislation to limit the abuse
of our telephone lines by computers, the abuse of mail service by advertisers, and the
pollution of our sewage systems by industrial wastes. The regulation of convivial
institutions sets limits to their use; as one moves from the convivial to the manipulative
end of the spectrum, the rules progressively call for unwilling consumption or
participation. The different cost of acquiring clients is just one of the characteristics
which distinguish convivial from manipulative institutions.

At both extremes of the spectrum we find service institutions, but on the right the service
is imposed manipulation, and the client is made the victim of advertising, aggression,
indoctrination, imprisonment, or electroshock. On the left the service is amplified
opportunity within formally defined limits, while the client remains a free agent. Right-
wing institutions tend to be highly complex and costly production processes in which
much of the elaboration and expense is concerned with convincing consumers that they
cannot live without the product or the treatment offered by the institution. Left-wing
institutions tend to be networks which facilitate client-initiated communication or
cooperation.

The manipulative institutions of the right are either socially or psychologically
"addictive." Social addiction, or escalation, consists in the tendency to prescribe
increased treatment if smaller quantities have not yielded the desired results. Psycho-
logical addiction, or habituation, results when consumers become hooked on the need for
more and more of the process or product. The self-activated institutions of the left tend to
be self-limiting. Unlike production processes which identify satisfaction with the mere
act of consumption, these networks serve a purpose beyond their own repeated use. An
individual picks up the telephone when he wants to say something to someone else, and
hangs up when the desired communication is over. He does not, teen-agers excepted, use
the telephone for the sheer pleasure of talking into the receiver. If the telephone is not the
best way to get in touch, people will write a letter or take a trip. Right-wing institutions,
as we can see clearly in the case of schools, both invite compulsively repetitive use and
frustrate alternative ways of achieving similar results.

Toward, but not at, the left on the institutional spectrum, we can locate enterprises which
compete with others in their own field, but have not begun notably to engage in
advertising. Here we find hand laundries, small bakeries, hairdressers, and-to speak of
professionals-some lawyers and music teachers. Characteristically left of center, then, are
self-employed persons who have institutionalized their services but not their publicity.

Deschooling Society

Page # 40

They acquire clients through their personal touch and the comparative quality of their
services.

Hotels and cafeterias are somewhat closer to the center. The big chains like Hilton-which
spend huge amounts on selling their image-often behave as if they were running
institutions of the right. Yet Hilton and Sheraton enterprises do not usually offer anything
more-in fact, they often give less-than similarly priced, independently managed lodgings.
Essentially, a hotel sign beckons to a traveler in the manner of a road sign. It says, "Stop,
here is a bed for you," rather than, "You should prefer a hotel bed to a park bench!"

The producers of staples and most perishable consumer goods belong in the middle of our
spectrum. They fill generic demands and add to the cost of production and distribution
whatever the market will bear in advertising costs for publicity and special packaging.

The more basic the product-be it goods or services-the more does competition tend to
limit the sales cost of the item.

Most manufacturers of consumer goods have moved much further to the right. Both
directly and indirectly, they produce demands for accessories which boost real purchase
price far beyond production cost. General Motors and Ford produce means of
transportation, but they also, and more importantly, manipulate public taste in such a way
that the need for transportation is expressed as a demand for private cars rather than
public buses. They sell the desire to control a machine, to race at high speeds in luxurious
comfort, while also offering the fantasy at the end of the road. What they sell, however, is
not just a matter of uselessly big motors, superfluous gadgetry, or the new extras forced
on the manufacturers by Ralph Nader and the clean-air lobbyists. The list price includes
souped-up engines, air-conditioning, safety belts, and exhaust controls; but other costs
not openly declared to the driver are also involved: the corporation's advertising and sales
expenses, fuel, maintenance and parts, insurance, interest on credit, as well as less
tangible costs like loss of time, temper, and breathable air in our traffic-congested cities.

An especially interesting corollary to our discussion of socially useful institutions is the
system of "public" highways. This major element of the total cost of automobiles
deserves lengthier treatment, since it leads directly to the rightist institution in which I am
most interested, namely, the school.

False Public Utilities

The highway system is a network for locomotion across relatively large distances. As a
network, it appears to belong on the left of the institutional spectrum. But here we must
make a distinction which will clarify both the nature of highways and the nature of true
public utilities. Genuinely all-purpose roads are true public utilities. Superhighways are
private preserves, the cost of which has been partially foisted upon the public.

Telephone, postal, and highway systems are all networks, and none of them is free.

Access to the telephone network is limited by time charges on each call. These rates are
relatively small and could be reduced without changing the nature of the system. Use of

Deschooling Society

Page #41

the telephone system is not in the least limited by what is transmitted, although it is best
used by those who can speak coherent sentences in the language of the other party-an
ability universally possessed by those who wish to use the network. Postage is usually
cheap. Use of the postal system is slightly limited by the price of pen and paper, and
somewhat more by the ability to write. Still, when someone who does not know how to
write has a relative or friend to whom he can dictate a letter, the postal system is at his
service, as it is if he wants to ship a recorded tape.

The highway system does not similarly become available to someone who merely learns
to drive. The telephone and postal networks exist to serve those who wish to use them,
while the highway system mainly serves as an accessory to the private automobile. The
former are true public utilities, whereas the latter is a public service to the owners of cars,
trucks, and buses. Public utilities exist for the sake of communication among men;
highways, like other institutions of the right, exist for the sake of a product. Auto
manufacturers, we have already observed, produce simultaneously both cars and the
demand for cars. They also produce the demand for multilane highways, bridges, and
oilfields. The private car is the focus of a cluster of right-wing institutions. The high cost
of each element is dictated by elaboration of the basic product, and to sell the basic
product is to hook society on the entire package.

To plan a highway system as a true public utility would discriminate against those for
whom velocity and individualized comfort are the primary transportation values, in favor
of those who value fluidity and destination. It is the difference between a far-flung
network with maximum access for travelers and one which offers only privileged access
to restricted areas.

Transferring a modern institution to the developing nations provides the acid test of its
quality. In very poor countries roads are usually just good enough to permit transit by
special, high-axle trucks loaded with groceries, livestock, or people. This kind of country
should use its limited resources to build a spiderweb of trails extending to every region
and should restrict imports to two or three different models of highly durable vehicles
which can manage all trails at low speed. This would simplify maintenance and the
stocking of spare parts, permit the operation of these vehicles around the clock, and
provide maximum fluidity and choice of destination to all citizens. This would require the
engineering of all-purpose vehicles with the simplicity of the Model T, making use of the
most modern alloys to guarantee durability, with a built-in speed limit of not more than
fifteen miles per hour, and strong enough to run on the roughest terrain. Such vehicles are
not on the market because there is no demand for them. As a matter of fact, such a
demand would have to be cultivated, quite possibly under the protection of strict
legislation. At present, whenever such a demand is even slightly felt, it is quickly snuffed
out by counterpublicity aimed at universal sales of the machines which currently extract
from U.S. taxpayers the money needed for building superhighways.

In order to "improve" transportation, all countries-even the poorest-now plan highway
systems designed for the passenger cars and high-speed trailers which fit the velocity-
conscious minority of producers and consumers in the elite classes. This approach is

Deschooling Society

Page # 42

frequently rationalized as a saving of the most precious resource of a poor country: the
time of the doctor, the school inspector, or the public administrator. These men, of
course, serve almost exclusively the same people who have, or hope one day to have, a
car. Local taxes and scarce international exchange are wasted on false public utilities.

"Modem" technology transferred to poor countries falls into three large categories:
goods, factories which make them, and service institutions— principally schools— which
make men into modem producers and consumers. Most countries spend by far the largest
proportion of their budget on schools. The school-made graduates then create a demand
for other conspicuous utilities, such as industrial power, paved highways, modern
hospitals, and airports, and these in turn create a market for the goods made for rich
countries and, after a while, the tendency to import obsolescent factories to produce them.

Of all "false utilities," school is the most insidious. Highway systems produce only a
demand for cars. Schools create a demand for the entire set of modern institutions which
crowd the right end of the spectrum. A man who questioned the need for high, ways
would be written off as a romantic; the man who questions the need for school is
immediately attacked as either heartless or imperialist.

Schools as False Public Utilities

Like highways, schools, at first glance, give the impression of being equally open to all
comers. They are, in fact, open only to those who consistently renew their credentials.

Just as highways create the impression that their present level of cost per year is
necessary if people are to move, so schools are presumed essential for attaining the
competence required by a society which uses modern technology. We have exposed
speedways as spurious public utilities by noting their dependence on private automobiles.
Schools are based upon the equally spurious hypothesis that learning is the result of
curricular teaching.

Highways result from a perversion of the desire and need for mobility into the demand
for a private car. Schools themselves pervert the natural inclination to grow and learn into
the demand for instruction. Demand for manufactured maturity is a far greater abnegation
of self-initiated activity than the demand for manufactured goods. Schools are not only to
the right of highways and cars; they belong near the extreme of the institutional spectrum
occupied by total asylums. Even the producers of body counts kill only bodies. By
making men abdicate the responsibility for their own growth, school leads many to a kind
of spiritual suicide.

Highways are paid for in part by those who use them, since tolls and gasoline taxes are
extracted only from drivers. School, on the other hand, is a perfect system of regressive
taxation, where the privileged graduates ride on the back of the entire paying public.
School puts a head tax on promotion. The underconsumption of highway mileage is not
nearly so costly as the underconsumption of schooling. The man who does not own a car
in Los Angeles may be almost immobilized, but if he can somehow manage to reach a
work place, he can get and hold a job. The school dropout has no alternative route. The

Deschooling Society

Page # 43

suburbanite with his new Lincoln and his country cousin who drives a beat-up jalopy get
essentially the same use out of the highway, even though one man's car costs thirty times
more than the other's. The value of a man's schooling is a function of the number of years
he has completed and of the costliness of the schools he has attended. The law compels
no one to drive, whereas it obliges everyone to go to school.

The analysis of institutions according to their present placement on a left-right continuum
enables me to clarify my belief that fundamental social change must begin with a change
of consciousness about institutions and to explain why the dimension of a viable future
turns on the rejuvenation of institutional style.

During the sixties institutions born in different decades since the French Revolution
simultaneously reached old age; public school systems founded in the time of Jefferson
or of AtatYrk, along with others which started after World War II, all became
bureaucratic, self-justifying, and manipulative. The same thing happened to systems of
social security, to labor unions, major churches and diplomacies, the care of the aged, and
the disposal of the dead.

Today, for instance, the school systems of Colombia, Britain, the U.S.S.R., and the U.S.
resemble each other more closely than U.S. schools of the late 1890's resembled either
today's or their contemporaries in Russia. Today all schools are obligatory, open-ended,
and competitive. The same convergence in institutional style affects health care,
merchandising, personnel administration, and political life. All these institutional
processes tend to pile up at the manipulative end of the spectrum.

A merger of world bureaucracies results from this convergence of institutions. The style,
the ranking systems, and the paraphernalia (from textbook to computer) are standardized
on the planning boards of Costa Rica or Afghanistan after the model of Western Europe.

Everywhere these bureaucracies seem to focus on the same task: promoting the growth of
institutions of the right. They are concerned with the making of things, the making of
ritual rules, and the making-and reshaping— of "executive truth," the ideology or fiat
which establishes the current value which should be attributed to their product.
Technology provides these bureaucracies with increasing power on the right hand of
society. The left hand of society seems to wither, not because technology is less capable
of increasing the range of human action, and providing time for the play of individual
imagination and personal creativity, but because such use of technology does not increase
the power of an elite which administers it. The postmaster has no control over the
substantive use of the mails, the switchboard operator or Bell Telephone executive has no
power to stop adultery, murder, or subversion from being planned over his network.

At stake in the choice between the institutional right and left is the very nature of human
life. Man must choose whether to be rich in things or in the freedom to use them. He must
choose between alternate styles of life and related production schedules.

Deschooling Society

Page # 44

Aristotle had already discovered that "making and acting" are different, so different, in
fact, that one never includes the other. "For neither is acting a way of making-nor making

a way of truly acting. Architecture [techne] is a way of making of bringing

something into being whose origin is in the maker and not in the thing. Making has
always an end other than itself, action not; for good action itself is its end. Perfection in
making is an art, perfection in acting is a virtue." [Nichomachean Ethics, 1 1 40.] The
word which Aristotle employed for making was "poesis, " and the word he employed for
doing, "praxis. " A move to the right implies that an institution is being restructured to
increase its ability to "make," while as it moves to the left, it is being restructured to
allow increased "doing" or "praxis. " Modern technology has increased the ability of man
to relinquish the "making" of things to machines, and his potential time for "acting"" has
increased. "Making" the necessities of life has ceased to take up his time. Unemployment
is the result of this modernization: it is the idleness of a man for whom there is nothing to
"make" and who does not know what to "do"— that is, how to "act." Unemployment is the
sad idleness of a man who, contrary to Aristotle, believes that making things, or working,
is virtuous and that idleness is bad. Unemployment is the experience of the man who has
succumbed to the Protestant ethic. Leisure, according to Weber, is necessary for man to
be able to work. For Aristotle, work is necessary for man to have leisure.

Technology provides man with discretionary time he can fill either with making or with
doing. The choice between sad unemployment and joyful leisure is now open for the
entire culture. It depends on the institutional style the culture chooses. This choice would
have been unthinkable in an ancient culture built either on peasant agriculture or on
slavery. It has become inevitable for postindustrial man.

One way to fill available time is to stimulate increased demands for the consumption of
goods and, simultaneously, for the production of services. The former implies an
economy which provides an ever-growing array of ever newer things which can be made,
consumed, wasted, and recycled. The latter implies the futile attempt to "make" virtuous
actions into the products of "service" institutions. This leads to the identification of
schooling and education, of medical service and health, of program-watching and
entertainment, of speed and effective locomotion. This first option now goes under the
name of development.

The radically alternative way to fill available time is a limited range of more durable
goods and to provide access to institutions which can increase the opportunity and
desirability of human interaction.

A durable-goods economy is precisely the contrary of an economy based on planned
obsolescence. A durable-goods economy means a constraint on the bill of goods. Goods
would have to be such that they provided the maximum opportunity to "do" something
with them: items made for self-assembly, self-help, reuse, and repair.

The complement to a durable, repairable, and reusable bill of goods is not an increase of
institutionally produced services, but rather an institutional framework which constantly
educates to action, participation, and self-help. The movement of our society from the

Deschooling Society

Page # 45

present— in which all institutions gravitate toward post-industrial bureaucracy— to a future
of postindustrial conviviality— in which the intensity of action would prevail over
production— must begin with a renewal of style in the service institutions— and, first of all,
with a renewal of education. A future which is desirable and feasible depends on our
willingness to invest our technological know-how into the growth of convivial
institutions. In the field of educational research, this amounts to the request for a reversal
of present trends.

Deschooling Society

Page # 46

5

Irrational Consistencies*

  • This chapter was presented originally at a meeting of the American Educational
    Research Association, in New York City, February 6, 1971.

I believe that the contemporary crisis of education demands that we review the very idea
of publicly prescribed learning, rather than the methods used in its enforcement. The
dropout rate— especially of junior-high-school students and elementary- school teachers—
points to a grass-roots demand for a completely fresh look. The "classroom practitioner"
who considers himself a liberal teacher is increasingly attacked from all sides. The free-
school movement, confusing discipline with indoctrination, has painted him into the role
of a destructive authoritarian. The educational technologist consistently demonstrates the
teacher's inferiority at measuring and modifying behavior. And the school administration
for which he works forces him to bow to both Summerhill and Skinner, making it
obvious that compulsory learning cannot be a liberal enterprise. No wonder that the
desertion rate of teachers is overtaking that of their students.

America's commitment to the compulsory education of its young now reveals itself to be
as futile as the pretended American commitment to compulsory democratization of the
Vietnamese. Conventional schools obviously cannot do it. The free-school movement
entices unconventional educators, but ultimately does so in support of the conventional
ideology of schooling. And the promises of educational technologists, that their research
and development— if adequately funded— can offer some kind of final solution to the
resistance of youth to compulsory learning, sound as confident and prove as fatuous as
the analogous promises made by the military technologists.

The criticism directed at the American school system by the behaviorists and that coming
from the new breed of radical educators seem radically opposed. The behaviorists apply
educational research to the "induction of autotelic instruction through individualized
learning packages." Their style clashes with the nondirective cooption of youth into
liberated communes established under the supervision of adults. Yet, in historical
perspective, these two are just contemporary manifestations of the seemingly
contradictory yet really complementary goals of the public school system. From the
beginning of this century, the schools have been protagonists of social control on the one
hand and free cooperation on the other, both placed at the service of the "good society,"
conceived of as a highly organized and smoothly working corporate structure. Under the
impact of intense urbanization, children became a natural resource to be molded by the

Deschooling Society

Page # 47

schools and fed into the industrial machine. Progressive politics and the cult of efficiency
converged in the growth of the U.S. public school. Vocational guidance and the junior
high school were two important results of this kind of thinking. [
See Joel Spring,
Education and the Rise of the Corporate State, Cuademo No. 50. Centro Intercultural de
Documentacin, Cuernavaca, Mexico, 1971.]

It appears, therefore, that the attempt to produce specified behavioral changes which can
be measured and for which the processor can be held accountable is just one side of a
coin, whose other side is the pacification of the new generation within specially
engineered enclaves which will seduce them into the dream world of their elders. These
pacified in society are well described by Dewey, who wants us to "make each one of our
schools an embryonic community life, active with types of occupations that reflect the
life of the larger society, and permeate it with the spirit of art, history and science." In
this historical perspective, it would be a grave mistake to interpret the current three-
cornered controversy between the school establishment, the educational technologists and
the free schools as the prelude to a revolution in education. This controversy reflects
rather a stage of an attempt to escalate an old dream into fact, and to finally make all
valuable learning the result of professional teaching. Most educational alternatives
proposed converge toward goals which are immanent in the production of the cooperative
man whose individual needs are met by means of his specialization in the American
system: They are oriented toward the improvement of what-for lack of a better phrase— I
call the schooled society. Even the seemingly radical critics of the school system are not
willing to abandon the idea that they have an obligation to the young, especially to the
poor, an obligation to process them, whether by love or by fear, into a society which
needs disciplined specialization as much from its producers as from its consumers and
also their full commitment to the ideology which puts economic growth first.

Dissent veils the contradictions inherent in the very idea of school. The established
teachers unions, the technological wizards, and the educational liberation movement
reinforce the commitment of the entire society to the fundamental axioms of a schooled
world, somewhat in the manner in which many peace and protest movements reinforce
the commitments of their members— be they black, female, young, or poor— to seek justice
through the growth of the gross national income.

Some of the tenets which now go unchallenged are easy to list. There is, first, the shared
belief that behavior which has been acquired in the sight of a pedagogue is of special
value to the pupil and of special benefit to society. This is related to the assumption that
social man is bom only in adolescence, and properly born only if he matures in the
school-womb, which some want to gentle by permissiveness, others to stuff with gadgets,
and still others to varnish with a liberal tradition. And there is, finally, a shared view of
youth which is psychologically romantic and politically conservative. According to this
view, changes in society must be brought about by burdening the young with the
responsibility of transforming it-but only after their eventual release from school. It is
easy for a society founded on such tenets to build up a sense of its responsibility for the
education of the new generation, and this inevitably means that some men may set,
specify, and evaluate the personal goals of others. In a "passage from an imaginary

Deschooling Society

Page # 48

Chinese encyclopedia," Jorge Luis Borges tries to evoke the sense of giddiness such an
attempt must produce. He tells us that animals are divided into the following classes: "(a)
those belonging to the emperor, (b) those that are embalmed, (c) those that are
domesticated, (d) the suckling pigs, (e) the sirens, (f) fabulous ones, (g) the roaming
dogs, (h) those included in the present classification, (i) those that drive themselves crazy,
(]) innumerable ones, (k) those painted with a very fine brush of camel hair, (1) et cetera,
(m) those who have just broken the jug, (n) those who resemble flies from afar." Now,
such a taxonomy does not come into being unless somebody feels it can serve his
purpose: in this case, I suppose, that somebody was a tax collector. For him, at least, this
taxonomy of beasts must have made sense, the same way in which the taxonomy of
educational objectives makes sense to scientific authors.

In the peasant, the vision of men with such inscrutable logic, empowered to assess his
cattle, must have induced a chilling sense of impotence. Students, for analogous reasons,
tend to feel paranoiac when they seriously submit to a curriculum. Inevitably they are
even more frightened than my imaginary Chinese peasant, because it is their life goals
rather than their life-stock which is being branded with an inscrutable sign.

This passage of Borges is fascinating, because it evokes the logic of irrational
consistency which makes Kafka's and Koestler's bureaucracies so sinister yet so evocative
of everyday life. Irrational consistency mesmerizes accomplices who are engaged in
mutually expedient and disciplined exploitation. It is the logic generated by bureaucratic
behavior. And it becomes the logic of a society which demands that the managers of its
educational institutions be held publicly accountable for the behavioral modification they
produce in their clients. Students who can be motivated to value the educational packages
which their teachers obligate them to consume are comparable to Chinese peasants who
can fit their flocks into the tax form provided by Borges.

At some time during the last two generations a commitment to therapy triumphed in
American culture, and teachers came to be regarded as the therapists whose ministrations
all men need, if they wish to enjoy the equality and freedom with which, according to the
Constitution, they are born. Now the teacher-therapists go on to propose lifelong
educational treatment as the next step. The style of this treatment is under discussion:
Should it take the form of continued adult classroom attendance? Electronic ecstasy? Or
periodic sensitivity sessions? All educators are ready to conspire to push out the walls of
the classroom, with the goal of transforming the entire culture into a school.

The American controversy over the future of education, behind its rhetoric and noise, is
more conservative than the discourse in other areas of public policy. On foreign affairs, at
least, an organized minority constantly reminds us that the United States must renounce
its role as the world's policeman. Radical economists, and now even their less radical
teachers, question aggregate growth as a desirable goal. There are lobbies for prevention
over cure in medicine and others in favor of fluidity over speed in transportation. Only in
the field of education do the articulate voices demanding a radical deschooling of society
remain so dispersed. There is a lack of cogent argument and of mature leadership aiming
at the disestablishment of any and all institutions which serve the purpose of compulsory

Deschooling Society

Page # 49

learning. For the moment, the radical deschooling of society is still a cause without a
party. This is especially surprising in a time of growing, though chaotic, resistance to all
forms of institutionally planned instruction on the part of those aged twelve to seventeen.

Educational innovators still assume that educational institutions function like funnels for
the programs they package. For my argument it is irrelevant whether these funnels take
the form of a classroom, a TV transmitter, or a "liberated zone." It is equally irrelevant
whether the packages purveyed are rich or poor, hot or cold, hard and measurable (like
Math III), or impossible to assess (like sensitivity). What counts is that education is
assumed to be the result of an institutional process managed by the educator. As long as
the relations continue to be those between a supplier and a consumer, educational
research will remain a circular process. It will amass scientific evidence in support of the
need for more educational packages and for their more deadly accurate delivery to the
individual customer, just as a certain brand of social science can prove the need for the
delivery of more military treatment.

An educational revolution depends on a twofold inversion: a new orientation for research
and a new understanding of the educational style of an emerging counterculture.

Operational research now seeks to optimize the efficiency of an inherited framework— a
framework which is itself never questioned. This framework has the syntactic structure of
a funnel for teaching packages. The syntactic alternative to it is an educational network or
web for the autonomous assembly of resources under the personal control of each learner.
This alternative structure of an educational institution now lies within the conceptual
blind spot of our operational research. If research were to focus on it, this would
constitute a true scientific revolution.

The blind spot of educational research reflects the cultural bias of a society in which
technological growth has been confused with technocratic control. For the technocrat the
value of an environment increases as more contacts between each man and his milieu can
be programmed. In this world the choices which are manageable for the observer or
planner converge with the choices possible for the observed so-called beneficiary.
Freedom is reduced to a selection among packaged commodities.

The emerging counterculture reaffirms the values of semantic content above the
efficiency of increased and more rigid syntax. It values the wealth of connotation above
the power of syntax to produce wealth. It values the unpredictable outcome of self-chosen
personal encounter above the certified quality of professional instruction. This
reorientation toward personal surprise rather than institutionally engineered values will be
disruptive of the established order until we dissociate the increasing availability of
technological tools which facilitate encounter from the increasing control of the
technocrat of what happens when people meet.

Our present educational institutions are at the service of the teacher's goals. The relational
structures we need are those which will enable each man to define himself by learning
and by contributing to the learning of others.

Deschooling Society

Page # 50

Deschooling Society

Page #51

6

Learning Webs

In a previous chapter I discussed what is becoming a common complaint about schools,
one that is reflected, for example, in the recent report of the Carnegie Commission: In
school registered students submit to certified teachers in order to obtain certificates of
their own; both are frustrated and both blame insufficient resources— money, time, or
buildings— for their mutual frustration.

Such criticism leads many people to ask whether it is possible to conceive of a different
style of learning. The same people, paradoxically, when pressed to specify how they
acquired what they know and value, will readily admit that they learned it more often
outside than inside school. Their knowledge of facts, their understanding of life and work
came to them from friendship or love, while viewing TV, or while reading, from
examples of peers or the challenge of a street encounter. Or they may have learned what
they know through the apprenticeship ritual for admission to a street gang or the initiation
to a hospital, newspaper city room, plumber's shop, or insurance office. The alternative to
dependence on schools is not the use of public resources for some new device which
"makes" people learn; rather it is the creation of a new style of educational relationship
between man and his environment. To foster this style, attitudes toward growing up, the
tools available for learning, and the quality and structure of daily life will have to change
concurrently.

Attitudes are already changing. The proud dependence on school is gone. Consumer
resistance increases in the knowledge industry. Many teachers and pupils, taxpayers and
employers, economists and policemen would prefer not to depend any longer on schools.
What prevents their frustration from shaping new institutions is a lack not only of
imagination but frequently also of appropriate language and of enlightened self-interest.
They cannot visualize either a deschooled society or educational institutions in a society
which has disestablished school.

In this chapter I intend to show that the inverse of school is possible: that we can depend
on self-motivated learning instead of employing teachers to bribe or compel the student
to find the time and the will to learn; that we can provide the learner with new links to the
world instead of continuing to funnel all educational programs through the teacher. I shall
discuss some of the general characteristics which distinguish schooling from learning and
outline four major categories of educational institutions which should appeal not only to
many individuals but also to many existing interest groups.

Deschooling Society

Page # 52

An Objection: Who Can Be Served by Bridges to Nowhere?

We are used to considering schools as a variable, dependent on the political and
economic structure. If we can change the style of political leadership, or promote the
interests of one class or another, or switch from private to public ownership of the means
of production, we assume the school system will change as well. The educational
institutions I will propose, however, are meant to serve a society which does not now
exist, although the current frustration with schools is itself potentially a major force to set
in motion change toward new social arrangements. An obvious objection has been raised
to this approach: Why channel energy to build bridges to nowhere, instead of marshaling
it first to change not the schools but the political and economic system?

This objection, however, underestimates the fundamental political and economic nature
of the school system itself, as well as the political potential inherent in any effective
challenge to it. In a basic sense, schools have ceased to be dependent on the ideology
professed by any government or market organization. Other basic institutions might differ
from one country to another: family, party, church, or press. But everywhere the school
system has the same structure, and everywhere its hidden curriculum has the same effect.
Invariably, it shapes the consumer who values institutional commodities above the
nonprofessional ministration of a neighbor.

Everywhere the hidden curriculum of schooling initiates the citizen to the myth that
bureaucracies guided by scientific knowledge are efficient and benevolent. Everywhere
this same curriculum instills in the pupil the myth that increased production will""
provide a better life. And everywhere it develops the habit of self-defeating consumption
of services and alienating production, the tolerance for institutional dependence, and the
recognition of institutional rankings. The hidden curriculum of school does all this in
spite of contrary efforts undertaken by teachers and no matter what ideology prevails.

In other words, schools are fundamentally alike in all countries, be they fascist,
democratic or socialist, big or small, rich or poor. This identity of the school system
forces us to recognize the profound world-wide identity of myth, mode of production,
and method of social control, despite the great variety of mythologies in which the myth
finds expression.

In view of this identity, it is illusory to claim that schools are, in any profound sense,
dependent variables. This means that to hope for fundamental change in the school
system as an effect of conventionally conceived social or economic change is also an
illusion. Moreover, this illusion grants the school— the reproductive organ of a consumer
society-almost unquestioned immunity.

It is at this point that the example of China becomes important. For three millennia,

China protected higher learning through a total divorce between the process of learning
and the privilege conferred by mandarin examinations. To become a world power and a

Deschooling Society

Page # 53

modern nation-state, China had to adopt the international style of schooling. Only
hindsight will allow us to discover if the Great Cultural Revolution will turn out to have
been the first successful attempt at deschooling the institutions of society.

Even the piecemeal creation of new educational agencies which were the inverse of
school would be an attack on the most sensitive link of a pervasive phenomenon, which is
organized by the state in all countries. A political program which does not explicitly
recognize the need for deschooling is not revolutionary; it is demagoguery calling for
more of the same. Any major political program of the seventies should be evaluated by
this measure: How clearly does it state the need for deschooling— and how clearly does it
provide guidelines for the educational quality of the society for which it aims?

The struggle against domination by the world market and big-power politics might be
beyond some poor communities or countries, but this weakness is an added reason for
emphasizing the importance of liberating each society through a reversal of its
educational structure, a change which is not beyond any society's means.

General Characteristics of New Formal Educational Institutions

A good educational system should have three purposes: it should provide all who want to
learn with access to available resources at any time in their lives; empower all who want
to share what they know to find those who want to learn it from them; and, finally,
furnish all who want to present an issue to the public with the opportunity to make their
challenge known. Such a system would require the application of constitutional
guarantees to education. Learners should not be forced to submit to an obligatory
curriculum, or to discrimination based on whether they possess a certificate or a diploma.
Nor should the public be forced to support, through a regressive taxation, a huge
professional apparatus of educators and buildings which in fact restricts the public's
chances for learning to the services the profession is willing to put on the market. It
should use modern technology to make free speech, free assembly, and a free press truly
universal and, therefore, fully educational.

Schools are designed on the assumption that there is a secret to everything in life; that the
quality of life depends on knowing that secret; that secrets can be known only in orderly
successions; and that only teachers can properly reveal these secrets. An individual with a
schooled mind conceives of the world as a pyramid of classified packages accessible only
to those who carry the proper tags. New educational institutions would break apart this
pyramid. Their purpose must be to facilitate access for the learner: to allow him to look
into the windows of the control room or the parliament, if he cannot get in by the door.
Moreover, such new institutions should be channels to which the learner would have
access without credentials or pedigree-public spaces in which peers and elders outside
his immediate horizon would become available.

I believe that no more than four— possibly even three— distinct "channels" or learning
exchanges could contain all the resources needed for real learning. The child grows up in
a world of things, surrounded by people who serve as models for skills and values. He

Deschooling Society

Page # 54

finds peers who challenge him to argue, to compete, to cooperate, and to understand; and
if the child is lucky, he is exposed to confrontation or criticism by an experienced elder
who really cares. Things, models, peers, and elders are four resources each of which
requires a different type of arrangement to ensure that everybody has ample access to it.

I will use the words "opportunity web" for "network" to designate specific ways to
provide access to each of four sets of resources. "Network" is often used, unfortunately,
to designate the channels reserved to material selected by others for indoctrination,
instruction, and entertainment. But it can also be used for the telephone or the postal
service, which are primarily accessible to individuals who want to send messages to one
another. I wish we had another word to designate such reticular structures for mutual
access, a word less evocative of entrapment, less degraded by current usage and more
suggestive of the fact that any such arrangement includes legal, organizational, and
technical aspects. Not having found such a term, I will try to redeem the one which is
available, using it as a synonym of "educational web."

What are needed are new networks, readily available to the public and designed to spread
equal opportunity for learning and teaching.

To give an example: The same level of technology is used in TV and in tape recorders.
All Latin- American countries now have introduced TV: in Bolivia the government has
financed a TV station, which was built six years ago, and there are no more than seven
thousand TV sets for four million citizens. The money now tied up in TV installations
throughout Latin America could have provided every fifth adult with a tape recorder. In
addition, the money would have sufficed to provide an almost unlimited library of
prerecorded tapes, with outlets even in remote villages, as well as an ample supply of
empty tapes.

This network of tape recorders, of course, would be radically different from the present
network of TV. It would provide opportunity for free expression: literate and illiterate
alike could record, preserve, disseminate, and repeat their opinions. The present
investment in TV, instead, provides bureaucrats, whether politicians or educators, with
the power to sprinkle the continent with institutionally produced programs which they-or
their sponsors— decide are good for or in demand by the people.

Technology is available to develop either independence and learning or bureaucracy and
teaching.

Four Networks

The planning of new educational institutions ought not to begin with the administrative
goals of a principal or president, or with the teaching goals of a professional educator, or
with the learning goals of any hypothetical class of people. It must not start with the
question, "What should someone learn?" but with the question, "What kinds of things and
people might learners want to be in contact with in order to learn?"

Deschooling Society

Page # 55

Someone who wants to learn knows that he needs both information and critical response
to its use from somebody else. Information can be stored in things and in persons. In a
good educational system access to things ought to be available at the sole bidding of the
learner, while access to informants requires, in addition, others' consent. Criticism can
also come from two directions: from peers or from elders, that is, from fellow learners
whose immediate interests match mine, or from those who will grant me a share in their
superior experience. Peers can be colleagues with whom to raise a question, companions
for playful and enjoyable (or arduous) reading or walking, challengers at any type of
game. Elders can be consultants on which skill to learn, which method to use, what
company to seek at a given moment. They can be guides to the right questions to be
raised among peers and to the deficiency of the answers they arrive at. Most of these
resources are plentiful. But they are neither conventionally perceived as educational
resources, nor is access to them for learning purposes easy, especially for the poor. We
must conceive of new relational structures which are deliberately set up to facilitate
access to these resources for the use of anybody who is motivated to seek them for his
education. Administrative, technological, and especially legal arrangements are required
to set up such web-like structures.

Educational resources are usually labeled according to educators' curricular goals. I
propose to do the contrary, to label four different approaches which enable the student to
gain access to any educational resource which may help him to define and achieve his
own goals:

  1. Reference Services to Educational Objects-which facilitate access to things or
    processes used for formal learning. Some of these things can be reserved for this purpose,
    stored in libraries, rental agencies, laboratories, and showrooms like museums and
    theaters; others can be in daily use in factories, airports, or on farms, but made available
    to students as apprentices or on off hours.

  2. Skill Exchanges— which permit persons to list their skills, the conditions under which
    they are willing to serve as models for others who want to learn these skills, and the
    addresses at which they can be reached.

  3. Peer-Matching— a communications network which permits persons to describe the
    learning activity in which they wish to engage, in the hope of finding a partner for the
    inquiry.

  4. Reference Services to Educators-at-Large— who can be listed in a directory giving the
    addresses and self-descriptions of professionals, paraprofessionals, and free-lancers,
    along with conditions of access to their services. Such educators, as we will see, could be
    chosen by polling or consulting their former clients.

Deschooling Society

Page # 56

Reference Services to Educational Objects

Things are basic resources for learning. The quality of the environment and the
relationship of a person to it will determine how much he learns incidentally. Formal
learning requires special access to ordinary things, on the one hand, or, on the other, easy
and dependable access to special things made for educational purposes. An example of
the former is the special right to operate or dismantle a machine in a garage. An example
of the latter is the general right to use an abacus, a computer, a book, a botanical garden,
or a machine withdrawn from production and placed at the full disposal of students.

At present, attention is focused on the disparity between rich and poor children in their
access to things and in the manner in which they can learn from them. OEO and other
agencies, following this approach, concentrate on equalizing chances, by trying to
provide more educational equipment for the poor. A more radical point of departure
would be to recognize that in the city rich and poor alike are artificially kept away from
most of the things that surround them. Children bom into the age of plastics and
efficiency experts must penetrate two barriers which obstruct their understanding: one
built into things and the other around institutions. Industrial design creates a world of
things that resist insight into their nature, and schools shut the learner out of the world of
things in their meaningful setting.

After a short visit to New York, a woman from a Mexican village told me she was
impressed by the fact that stores sold only wares heavily made up with cosmetics." I
understood her to mean that industrial products "speak" to their customers about their
allurements and not about their nature. Industry has surrounded people with artifacts
whose inner workings only specialists are allowed to understand. The nonspecialist is
discouraged from figuring out what makes a watch tick, or a tele-phone ring, or an
electric typewriter work, by being warned that it will break if he tries. He can be told
what makes a transistor radio work, but he cannot find out for himself. This type of
design tends to reinforce a noninventive society in which the experts find it progressively
easier to hide behind their expertise and beyond evaluation.

The man-made environment has become as inscrutable as nature is for the primitive. At
the same time, educational materials have been monopolized by school. Simple
educational objects have been expensively packaged by the knowledge industry. They
have become specialized tools for professional educators, and their cost has been inflated
by forcing them to stimulate either environments or teachers.

The teacher is jealous of the textbook he defines as his professional implement. The
student may come to hate the lab because he associates it with schoolwork. The
administrator rationalizes his protective attitude toward the library as a defense of costly
public equipment against those who would play with it rather than learn. In this
atmosphere the student too often uses the map, the lab, the encyclopedia, or the
microscope only at the rare moments when the curriculum tells him to do so. Even the
great classics become part of "sophomore year" instead of marking a new turn in a

Deschooling Society

Page# 57

person's life. School removes things from everyday use by labeling them educational
tools.

If we are to deschool, both tendencies must be reversed. The general physical
environment must be made accessible, and those physical learning resources which have
been reduced to teaching instruments must become generally available for self-directed
learning. Using things only as part of a curriculum can have an even worse effect than
just removing them from the general environment. It can corrupt the attitudes of pupils.

Games are a case in point. I do not mean the "games" of the physical education
department (such as football and basketball), which the schools use to raise income and
prestige and in which they have made a substantial capital investment. As the athletes
themselves are well aware, these enterprises, which take the form of warlike tournaments,
have undermined the playfulness of sports and are used to reinforce the competitive
nature of schools. Rather I have in mind the educational games which can provide a
unique way to penetrate formal systems. Set theory, linguistics, propositional logic,
geometry, physics, and even chemistry reveal themselves with little effort to certain
persons who play these games. A friend of mine went to a Mexican market with a game
called '"Wff 'n Proof," which consists of some dice on which twelve logical symbols are
imprinted. He showed children which two or three combinations constituted a well-
formed sentence, and inductively within the first hour some onlookers also grasped the
principle. Within a few hours of playfully conducting formal logical proofs, some
children are capable of introducing others to the fundamental proofs of propositional
logic. The others just walk away.

In fact, for some children such games are a special form of liberating education, since
they heighten their awareness of the fact that formal systems are built on changeable
axioms and that conceptual operations have a gamelike nature. They are also simple,
cheap, and-to a large extent-can be organized by the players themselves. Used outside
the curriculum such games provide an opportunity for identifying and developing unusual
talent, while the school psychologist will often identify those who have such talent as in
danger of becoming antisocial, sick, or unbalanced. Within school, when used in the form
of tournaments, games are not only removed from the sphere of leisure; they often
become tools used to translate playfulness into competition, a lack of abstract reasoning
into a sign of inferiority. An exercise which is liberating for some character types
becomes a straitjacket for others.

The control of school over educational equipment has still another effect. It increases
enormously the cost of such cheap materials. Once their use is restricted to scheduled
hours, professionals are paid to supervise their acquisition, storage, and use. Then
students vent their anger against the school on the equipment, which must be purchased
once again.

Paralleling the untouchability of teaching tools is the impenetrability of modern junk. In
the thirties any self-respecting boy knew how to repair an automobile, but now car
makers multiply wires and withhold manuals from everyone except specialized

Deschooling Society

Page # 58

mechanics. In a former era an old radio contained enough coils and condensers to build a
transmitter that would make all the neighborhood radios scream in feedback. Transistor
radios are more portable, but nobody dares to take them apart. To change this in the
highly industrialized countries will be immensely difficult; but at least in the Third World
we must insist on built-in educational qualities.

To illustrate my point, let me present a model: By spending ten million dollars it would
be possible to connect forty thousand hamlets in a country like Peru with a spiderweb of
six-foot-wide trails and maintain these, and, in addition, provide the country with 200,000
three-wheeled mechanical donkeys— five on the average for each hamlet. Few poor
countries of this size spend less than this yearly on cars and roads, both of which are now
restricted mainly to the rich and their employees, while poor people remain trapped in
their villages. Each of these simple but durable little vehicles would cost $125— half of
which would pay for transmission and a six-horsepower motor. A "donkey" could make
15 mph, and it can carry loads of 850 pounds (that is, most things besides tree trunks and
steel beams which are ordinarily moved).

The political appeal of such a transportation system to a peasantry is obvious. Equally
obvious is the reason why those who hold power— and thereby automatically have a car-
are not interested in spending money on trails and in clogging roads with engine-driven
donkeys. The universal donkey could work only if a country's leaders were willing to
impose a national speed limit of, say, twenty-five miles an hour and adapt its public
institutions to this. The model could not work if conceived only as a stopgap.

This is not the place to elaborate on the political, social, economic, financial, and
technical feasibility of this model. I wish only to indicate that educational considerations
may be of prime importance when choosing such an alternative to capital, intensive
transport. By raising the unit cost per donkey by some 20 percent it would become
possible to plan the production of all its parts in such a manner that, as far as possible,
each future owner would spend a month or two making and understanding his machine
and would be able to repair it. With this additional cost it would also be possible to
decentralize production into dispersed plants. The added benefits would result not only
from including educational costs in the construction process. Even more significantly, a
durable motor which practically anyone could leam to repair and which could be used as
a plow and pump by somebody who understood it would provide much higher
educational benefits than the inscrutable engines of the advanced countries.

Not only the junk but also the supposedly public places of the modern city have become
impenetrable. In American society, children are excluded from most things and places on
the grounds that they are private. But even in societies which have declared an end to
private property children are kept away from the same places and things because they are
considered the special domain of professionals and dangerous to the uninitiated. Since the
last generation the railroad yard has become as inaccessible as the fire station. Yet with a
little ingenuity it should not be difficult to provide for safety in such places. To deschool
the artifacts of education will require making the artifacts and processes available— and
recognizing their educational value. Certainly, some workers would find it inconvenient

Deschooling Society

Page # 59

to be accessible to learners; but this inconvenience must be balanced against the
educational gains.

Private cars could be banned from Manhattan. Five years ago it was unthinkable. Now
certain New York streets are closed off at odd hours, and this trend will probably
continue. Indeed, most cross-streets should be closed to automotive traffic and parking
should be forbidden everywhere. In a city opened up to people, teaching materials which
are now locked up in store-rooms and laboratories could be dispersed into independently
operated storefront depots which children and adults could visit without the danger of
being run over.

If the goals of learning were no longer dominated by schools and schoolteachers, the
market for learners would be much more various and the definition of "educational
artifacts" would be less restrictive. There could be tool shops, libraries, laboratories, and
gaming rooms. Photo labs and offset presses would allow neighborhood newspapers to
flourish. Some storefront learning centers could contain viewing booths for closed-circuit
television, others could feature office equipment for use and for repair. The jukebox or
the record player would be commonplace, with some specializing in classical music,
others in international folk tunes, others in jazz. Film clubs would compete with each
other and with commercial television. Museum outlets could be networks for circulating
exhibits of works of art, both old and new, originals and reproductions, perhaps
administered by the various metropolitan museums.

The professional personnel needed for this network would be much more like custodians,
museum guides, or reference librarians than like teachers. From the comer biology store,
they could refer their clients to the shell collection in the museum or indicate the next
showing of biology videotapes in a certain viewing booth. They could furnish guides for
pest control, diet, and other kinds of preventive medicine. They could refer those who
needed advice to "elders" who could provide it.

Two distinct approaches can be taken to financing a network of "learning objects." A
community could determine a maximum budget for this purpose and arrange for all parts
of the network to be open to all visitors at reasonable hours. Or the community could
decide to provide citizens with limited entitlements, according to their age group, which
would give them special access to certain materials which are both costly and scarce,
while leaving other, simpler materials available to everyone.

Finding resources for materials made specifically for education is only one— and perhaps
the least costly— aspect of building an educational world. The money now spent on the
sacred paraphernalia of the school ritual could be freed to provide all citizens with greater
access to the real life of the city. Special tax incentives could be granted to those who
employed children between the ages of eight and fourteen for a couple of hours each day
if the conditions of employment were humane ones. We should return to the tradition of
the bar mitzvah or confirmation. By this I mean we should first restrict, and later
eliminate, the disenfranchisement of the young and permit a boy of twelve to become a
man fully responsible for his participation in the life of the community. Many "school-

Deschooling Society

Page # 60

age" people know more about their neighborhood than social workers or councilmen. Of
course, they also ask more embarrassing questions and propose solutions which threaten
the bureaucracy. They should be allowed to come of age so that they could put their
knowledge and fact-finding ability to work in the service of a popular government.

Until recently the dangers of school were easily underestimated in comparison with the
dangers of an apprenticeship in the police force, the fire department, or the entertainment
industry. It was easy to justify schools at least as a means to protect youth. Often this
argument no longer holds. I recently visited a Methodist church in Harlem occupied by a
group of armed Young Lords in protest against the death of Julio Rodan, a Puerto Rican
youth found hanged in his prison cell. I knew the leaders of the group, who had spent a
semester in Cuernavaca. When I wondered why one of them, Juan, was not among them,

I was told that he had "gone back on heroin and to the State University."

Planning, incentives, and legislation can be used to unlock the educational potential
within our society's huge investment in plants and equipment. Full access to educational
objects will not exist so long as business firms are allowed to combine the legal
protections which the Bill of Rights reserves to the privacy of individuals with the
economic power conferred upon them by their millions of customers and thousands of
employees, stockholders, and suppliers. Much of the world's know-how and most of its
productive processes and equipment are locked within the walls of business firms, away
from their customers, employees, and stockholders, as well as from the general public,
whose laws and facilities allow them to function. Money now spent on advertising in
capitalist countries could be redirected toward education in and by General Electric,
NBC-TV, or Budweiser beer. That is, the plants and offices should be reorganized so that
their daily operations could be more accessible to the public in ways that would make
learning possible; and, indeed, ways might be found to pay the companies for the learning
people acquired from them.

An even more valuable body of scientific objects and data may be withheld from general
access— and even from qualified scientists— under the guise of national security. Until
recently science was the one forum which functioned like an anarchist's dream. Each man
capable of doing research had more or less the same opportunity of access to its tools and
to a hearing by the community of peers. Now bureaucratization and organization have
placed much of science beyond public reach. Indeed, what used to be an international
network of scientific information has been splintered into an arena of competing teams.
The members as well as the artifacts of the scientific community have been locked into
national and corporate programs oriented toward practical achievement, to the radical
impoverishment of the men who support these nations and corporations.

In a world which is controlled and owned by nations and corporations, only limited
access to educational objects will ever be possible. But increased access to those objects
which can be shared for educational purposes may enlighten us enough to help us to
break through these ultimate political barriers. Public schools transfer control over the
educational uses of objects from private to professional hands. The institutional inversion
of schools could empower the individual to reclaim the right to use them for education. A

Deschooling Society

Page# 61

truly public kind of ownership might begin to emerge if private or corporate control over
the educational aspect of "things" were brought to the vanishing point.

Skill Exchanges

A guitar teacher, unlike a guitar, can be neither classified in a museum nor owned by the
public nor rented from an educational warehouse. Teachers of skills belong to a different
class of resources from objects needed to learn a skill. This is not to say that they are
indispensable in every case. I can rent not only a guitar but also taped guitar lessons and
illustrated chord charts, and with these things I can teach myself to play the guitar.

Indeed, this arrangement may have advantages-if the available tapes are better than the
available teachers, or if the only time I have for learning the guitar is late at night, or if
the tunes I wish to play are unknown in my country, or if I am shy and prefer to fumble
along in privacy.

Skill teachers must be listed and contacted through a different kind of channel from that
of things. A thing is available at the bidding of the user— or could be— whereas a person
formally becomes a skill resource only when he consents to do so, and he can also restrict
time, place, and method as he chooses.

Skill teachers must be also distinguished from peers from whom one would learn. Peers
who wish to pursue a common inquiry must start from common interests and abilities;
they get together to exercise or improve a skill they share: basketball, dancing,
constructing a camp site, or discussing the next election. The first transmission of a skill,
on the other hand, involves bringing together someone who has the skill and someone
who does not have it and wants to acquire it.

A "skill model" is a person who possesses a skill and is willing to demonstrate its
practice. A demonstration of this kind is frequently a necessary resource for a potential
learner. Modern inventions permit us to incorporate demonstration into tape, film, or
chart; yet one would hope personal demonstration will remain in wide demand, especially
in communication skills. Some ten thousand adults have learned Spanish at our Center at
Cuernavaca— mostly highly motivated persons who wanted to acquire near-native fluency
in a second language. When they are faced with a choice between carefully programmed
instruction in a lab or drill sessions with two other students and a native speaker
following a rigid routine, most choose the second.

For most widely shared skills, a person who demonstrates the skill is the only human
resource we ever need or get. Whether in speaking or driving, in cooking or in the use of
communication equipment, we are often barely conscious of formal instruction and
learning, especially after our first experience of the materials in question. I see no reason
why other complex skills, such as the mechanical aspects of surgery and playing the
fiddle, of reading or the use of directories and catalogues, could not be learned in the
same way.

Deschooling Society

Page # 62

A well-motivated student who does not labor under a specific handicap often needs no
further human assistance than can be provided by someone who can demonstrate on
demand how to do what the learner wants to learn to do. The demand made of skilled
people that before demonstrating their skill they be certified as pedagogues is a result of
the insistence either that people learn what they do not want to know or that all people-
even those with a special handicap— learn certain things, at a given moment in their lives,
and preferably under specified circumstances.

What makes skills scarce on the present educational market is the institutional
requirement that those who can demonstrate them may not do so unless they are given
public trust, through a certificate. We insist that those who help others acquire a skill
should also know how to diagnose learning difficulties and be able to motivate people to
aspire to learn skills. In short, we demand that they be pedagogues. People who can
demonstrate skills will be plentiful as soon as we learn to recognize them outside the
teaching profession.

Where princelings are being taught, the parents' insistence that the teacher and the person
with skills be combined in one person is understandable, if no longer defensible. But for
all parents to aspire to have Aristotle for their Alexander is obviously self-defeating. The
person who can both inspire students and demonstrate a technique is so rare, and so hard
to recognize, that even princelings more often get a sophist than a true philosopher.

A demand for scarce skills can be quickly filled even if there are only small numbers of
people to demonstrate them; but such people must be easily available. During the forties
radio repairmen, most of them with no schooling in their work, were no more than two
years behind radios in penetrating the interior of Latin America. There they stayed until
transistor radios, which are cheap to purchase and impossible to repair, put them out of
business. Technical schools now fail to accomplish what repair, men of equally useful,
more durable radios could do as a matter of course.

Converging self-interests now conspire to stop a man from sharing his skill. The man
who has the skill profits from its scarcity and not from its reproduction. The teacher who
special, izes in transmitting the skill profits from the artisan's unwillingness to launch his
own apprentice into the field. The public is indoctrinated to believe that skills are
valuable and reliable only if they are the result of formal schooling. The job market
depends on making skills scarce and on keeping them scarce, either by proscribing their
unauthorized use and transmission or by making things which can be operated and
repaired only by those who have access to tools or information which are kept scarce.

Schools thus produce shortages of skilled persons. A good example is the diminishing
number of nurses in the United States, owing to the rapid increase of four-year B.S.
programs in nursing. Women from poorer families, who would formerly have enrolled in
a two- or three-year program, now stay out of the nursing profession altogether.

Insisting on the certification of teachers is another way of keeping skills scarce. If nurses
were encouraged to train nurses, and if nurses were employed on the basis of their proven

Deschooling Society

Page # 63

skill at giving injections, filling out charts, and giving medicine, there would soon be no
lack of trained nurses. Certification now tends to abridge the freedom of education by
converting the civil right to share one's knowledge into the privilege of academic
freedom, now conferred only on the employees of a school. To guarantee access to an
effective exchange of skills, we need legislation which generalizes academic freedom.
The right to teach any skill should come under the protection of freedom of speech. Once
restrictions on teaching are removed, they will quickly be removed from learning as well.

The teacher of skills needs some inducement to grant his services to a pupil. There are at
least two simple ways to begin to channel public funds to noncertified teachers. One way
would be to institutionalize the skill exchange by creating free skill centers open to the
public. Such centers could and should be established in industrialized areas, at least for
those skills which are fundamental prerequisites for entering certain apprenticeships—
such skills as reading, typing, keeping accounts, foreign languages, computer
programming and number manipulation, reading special languages such as that of
electrical circuits, manipulation of certain machinery, etc. Another approach would be to
give certain groups within the population educational currency good for attendance at
skill centers where other clients would have to pay commercial rates.

A much more radical approach would be to create a "bank" for skill exchange. Each
citizen would be given a basic credit with which to acquire fundamental skills. Beyond
that minimum, further credits would go to those who earned them by teaching, whether
they served as models in organized skill centers or did so privately at home or on the
playground. Only those who had taught others for an equivalent amount of time would
have a claim on the time of more advanced teachers. An entirely new elite would be
promoted, an elite of those who earned their education by sharing it.

Should parents have the right to earn skill credit for their children? Since such an
arrangement would give further advantage to the privileged classes, it might be offset by
granting a larger credit to the underprivileged. The operation of a skill exchange would
depend on the existence of agencies which would facilitate the development of directory
information and assure its free and inexpensive use. Such an agency might also provide
supplementary services of testing and certification and might help to enforce the
legislation required to break up and prevent monopolistic practices.

Fundamentally, the freedom of a universal skill exchange must be guaranteed by laws
which permit discrimination only on the basis of tested skills and not on the basis of
educational pedigree. Such a guarantee inevitably requires public control over tests which
may be used to qualify persons for the job market. Otherwise, it would be possible to
surreptitiously reintroduce complex batteries of tests at the work place itself which would
serve for social selection. Much could be done to make skill-testing objective, e.g.,
allowing only the operation of specific machines or systems to be tested. Tests of typing
(measured according to speed, number of errors, and whether or not the typist can work
from dictation), operation of an accounting system or of a hydraulic crane, driving,
coding into COBOL, etc., can easily be made objective.

Deschooling Society

Page # 64

In fact, many of the true skills which are of practical importance can be so tested. And for
the purposes of manpower management a test of a current skill level is much more useful
than the information that twenty years ago a person satisfied his teacher in a curriculum
in which typing, stenography, and accounting were taught. The very need for official
skill-testing can, of course, be questioned: I personally believe that freedom from undue
hurt to a man's reputation through labeling is better guaranteed by restricting than by
forbidding tests of competence.

Peer-Matching

At their worst, schools gather classmates into the same room and subject them to the
same sequence of treatment in math, citizenship, and spelling. At their best, they permit
each student to choose one of a limited number of courses. In any case, groups of peers
form around the goals of teachers. A desirable educational system would let each person
specify the activity for which he sought a peer.

School does offer children an opportunity to escape their homes and meet new friends.
But, at the same time, this process indoctrinates children with the idea that they should
select their friends from among those with whom they are put together. Providing the
young from their earliest age with invitations to meet, evaluate, and seek out others
would prepare them for a lifelong interest in seeking new partners for new endeavors.

A good chess player is always glad to find a close match, and one novice to find another.
Clubs serve their purpose. People who want to discuss specific books or articles would
probably pay to find discussion partners. People who want to play games, go on
excursions, build fish tanks, or motorize bicycles will go to considerable lengths to find
peers. The reward for their efforts is finding those peers. Good schools try to bring out
the common interests of their students registered in the same program. The inverse of
school would be an institution which increased the chances that persons who at a given
moment shared the same specific interest could meet— no matter what else they had in
common.

Skill-teaching does not provide equal benefits for both parties, as does the matching of
peers. The teacher of skills, as I have pointed out, must usually be offered some incentive
beyond the rewards of teaching. Skill-teaching is a matter of repeating drills over and
over and is, in fact, all the more dreary for those pupils who need it most. A skill
exchange needs currency or credits or other tangible incentives in order to operate, even
if the exchange itself were to generate a currency of its own. A peer-match, ing system
requires no such incentives, but only a communications network.

Tapes, retrieval systems, programmed instruction, and reproduction of shapes and sounds
tend to reduce the need for recourse to human teachers of many skills; they increase the
efficiency of teachers and the number of skills one can pick up in a lifetime. Parallel to
this runs an increased need to meet people interested in enjoying the newly acquired skill.
A student who has picked up Greek before her vacation would like to discuss in Greek
Cretan politics when she returns. A Mexican in New York wants to find other readers of

Deschooling Society

Page # 65

the paper Siempre — or of "Los Agachaclos, ” the most popular comic book. Somebody
else wants to meet peers who, like himself, would like to increase their interest in the
work of James Baldwin or of Bolivar.

The operation of a peer-matching network would be simple. The user would identify
himself by name and address and describe the activity for which he sought a peer. A
computer would send him back the names and addresses of all those who had inserted the
same description. It is amazing that such a simple utility has never been used on a broad
scale for publicly valued activity.

In its most rudimentary form, communication between client and computer could be
established by return mail. In big cities typewriter terminals could provide instantaneous
responses. The only way to retrieve a name and address from the computer would be to
list an activity for which a peer was sought. People using the system would become
known only to their potential peers.

A complement to the computer could be a network of bulletin boards and classified
newspaper ads, listing the activities for which the computer could not produce a match.
No names would have to be given. Interested readers would then introduce their names
into the system. A publicly supported peer-match network might be the only way to
guarantee the right of free assembly and to train people in the exercise of this most
fundamental civic activity.

The right of free assembly has been politically recognized and culturally accepted. We
should now understand that this right is curtailed by laws that make some forms of
assembly obligatory. This is especially the case with institutions which conscript
according to age group, class, or sex, and which are very time-consuming. The army is
one example. School is an even more outrageous one.

To deschool means to abolish the power of one person to oblige another person to attend
a meeting. It also means recognizing the right of any person, of any age or sex, to call a
meeting. This right has been drastically diminished by the institutionalization of
meetings. "Meeting" originally referred to the result of an individual's act of gathering.
Now it refers to the institutional product of some agency.

The ability of service institutions to acquire clients has far outgrown the ability of
individuals to be heard independently of institutional media, which respond to individuals
only if they are salable news. Peer-matching facilities should be available for individuals
who want to bring people together as easily as the village bell called the villagers to
council. School buildings— of doubtful value for conversion to other uses— could often
serve this purpose.

The school system, in fact, may soon face a problem which churches have faced before:
what to do with surplus space emptied by the defection of the faithful. Schools are as
difficult to sell as temples. One way to provide for their continued use would be to give
over the space to people from the neighborhood. Each could state what he would do in

Deschooling Society

Page # 66

the classroom and when, and a bulletin board would bring the available programs to the
attention of the inquirers. Access to "class" would be free-or purchased with educational
vouchers. The "teacher" could even be paid according to the number of pupils he could
attract for any full two-hour period. I can imagine that very young leaders and great
educators would be the two types most prominent in such a system. The same approach
could be taken toward higher education. Students could be furnished with educational
vouchers which entitled them to ten hours' yearly private consultation with the teacher of
their choice— and, for the rest of their learning, depend on the library, the peer-matching
network, and apprenticeships.

We must, of course, recognize the probability that such public matching devices would
be abused for exploitative and immoral purposes, just as the telephone and the mails have
been so abused. As with those networks, there must be some protection. I have proposed
elsewhere a matching system which would allow only pertinent printed information, plus
the name and address of the inquirer, to be used. Such a system would be virtually
foolproof against abuse. Other arrangements could allow the addition of any book, film,
TV program, or other item quoted from a special catalogue. Concern about the dangers of
the system should not make us lose sight of its far greater benefits.

Some who share my concern for free speech and assembly will argue that peer-matching
is an artificial means of bringing people together and would not be used by the poor— who
need it most. Some people become genuinely agitated when one suggests the setting up
of ad hoc encounters which are not rooted in the life of a local community. Others react
when one suggests using a computer to sort and match client-identified interests. People
cannot be drawn together in such an impersonal manner, they say. Common inquiry must
be rooted in a history of shared experience at many levels, and must grow out of this
experience-the development of neighborhood institutions, for example.

I sympathize with these objections, but I think they miss my point as well as their own. In
the first place, the return to neighborhood life as the primary center of creative expression
might actually work against the re-establishment of neighborhoods as political units.
Centering demands on the neighborhood may, in fact, neglect an important liberating
aspect of urban life— the ability of a person to participate simultaneously in several peer
groups. Also, there is an important sense in which people who have never lived together
in a physical community, may occasionally have far more experiences to share than those
who have known each other from childhood. The great religions have always recognized
the importance of far-off encounters, and the faithful have always found freedom through
them; pilgrimage, monasticism, the mutual support of temples and sanctuaries reflect this
awareness. Peer-matching could significantly help in making explicit the many potential
but suppressed communities of the city.

Local communities are valuable. They are also a vanishing reality as men progressively
let service institutions define their circles of social relationship. Milton Kotler in his
recent book has shown that the imperialism of "downtown" deprives the neighborhood of
its political significance. The protectionist attempt to resurrect the neighborhood as a
cultural unit only supports this bureaucratic imperialism. Far from artificially removing

Deschooling Society

Page # 67

men from their local contexts to join abstract groupings, peer-matching should encourage
the restoration of local life to cities from which it is now disappearing. A man who
recovers his initiative to call his fellows into meaningful conversation may cease to settle
for being separated from them by office protocol or suburban etiquette. Having once seen
that doing things together depends on deciding to do so, men may even insist that their
local communities become more open to creative political exchange.

We must recognize that city life tends to become immensely costly as city-dwellers must
be taught to rely for every one of their needs on complex institutional services. It is
extremely expensive to keep it even minimally livable. Peer-matching in the city could be
a first step toward breaking down the dependence of citizens on bureaucratic civic
services.

It would also be an essential step to providing new means of establishing public trust. In a
schooled society we have come to rely more and more on the professional judgment of
educators on the effect of their own work in order to decide whom we can or cannot trust:
we go to the doctor, lawyer, or psychologist because we trust that anybody with the
required amount of specialized educational treatment by other colleagues deserves our
confidence.

In a deschooled society professionals could no longer claim the trust of their clients on
the basis of their curricular pedigree, or ensure their standing by simply referring their
clients to other professionals who approved of their schooling. Instead of placing trust in
professionals, it should be possible, at any time, for any potential client to consult with
other experienced clients of a professional about their satisfaction with him by means of
another peer network easily set up by computer, or by a number of other means. Such
networks could be seen as public utilities which permitted students to choose their
teachers or patients their healers.

Professional Educators

As citizens have new choices, new chances for learning, their willingness to seek
leadership should increase. We may expect that they will experience more deeply both
their own independence and their need for guidance. As they are liberated from
manipulation by others, they should learn to profit from the discipline others have
acquired in a lifetime. Deschooling education should increase— rather than stifle— the
search for men with practical wisdom who would be willing to sustain the newcomer in
his educational adventure. As masters of their art abandon the claim to be superior
informants or skill models, their claim to superior wisdom will begin to ring true.

With an increasing demand for masters, their supply should also increase. As the
schoolmaster vanishes, conditions will arise which should bring forth the vocation of the
independent educator. This may seem almost a contradiction in terms, so thoroughly have
schools and teachers become complementary. Yet this is exactly what the development of
the first three educational exchanges would tend to result in— and what would be required

Deschooling Society

Page # 68

to permit their full exploitation— for parents and other '"natural educators" need guidance,
individual learners need assistance, and the networks need people to operate them.

Parents need guidance in directing their children on the road that leads to responsible
educational independence. Learners need experienced leadership when they encounter
rough terrain. These two needs are quite distinct: the first is a need for pedagogy, the
second for intellectual leadership in all other fields of knowledge. The first calls for
knowledge of human learning and of educational resources, the second for wisdom based
on experience in any kind of exploration. Both kinds of experience are indispensable for
effective educational endeavor. Schools package these functions into one role— and
render the independent exercise of any of them if not disreputable at least suspect.

Three types of special educational competence should, in fact, be distinguished: one to
create and operate the kinds of educational exchanges or networks outlined here; another
to guide students and parents in the use of these networks; and a third to act as primus
inter pares in undertaking difficult intellectual exploratory journeys. Only the former two
can be conceived of as branches of an independent profession: educational administrators
and pedagogical counselors. To design and operate the networks I have been describing
would not require many people, but it would require people with the most profound
understanding of education and administration, in a perspective quite different from and
even opposed to that of schools.

While an independent educational profession of this kind would welcome many people
whom the schools exclude, it would also exclude many whom the schools qualify. The
establishment and operation of educational networks would require some designers and
administrators, but not in the numbers or of the type required by the administration of
schools. Student discipline, public relations, hiring, supervising, and firing teachers
would have neither place nor counterpart in the networks I have been describing. Neither
would curriculum-making, textbook-purchasing, the maintenance of grounds and
facilities, or the supervision of interscholastic athletic competition. Nor would child
custody, lesson-planning, and record-keeping, which now take up so much of the time of
teachers, figure in the operation of educational networks. Instead, the operation of
learning webs would require some of the skills and attitudes now expected from the staff
of a museum, a library, an executive employment agency, or a maitre d'h™tel.

Today's educational administrators are concerned with controlling teachers and students
to the satisfaction of others -trustees, legislatures, and corporate executives. Network
builders and administrators would have to demonstrate genius at keeping themselves, and
others, out of people's way, at facilitating en-counters among students, skill models,
educational leaders, and educational objects. Many persons now attracted to teaching are
profoundly authoritarian and would not be able to assume this task: building educational
exchanges would mean making it easy for people— especially the young— to pursue goals
which might contradict the ideals of the traffic manager who makes the pursuit possible.

If the networks I have described could emerge, the educational path of each student
would be his own to follow, and only in retrospect would it take on the features of a

Deschooling Society

Page # 69

recognizable program. The wise student would periodically seek professional advice:
assistance to set a new goal, insight into difficulties encountered, choice between possible
methods. Even now, most persons would admit that the important services their teachers
have rendered them are such advice or counsel, given at a chance meeting or in a tutorial.
Pedagogues, in an unschooled world, would also come into their own, and be able to do
what frustrated teachers pretend to pursue today.

While network administrators would concentrate primarily on the building and
maintenance of roads providing access to resources, the pedagogue would help the
student to find the path which for him could lead fastest to his goal. If a student wanted to
learn spoken Cantonese from a Chinese neighbor, the pedagogue would be available to
judge their proficiency, and to help them select the textbook and methods most suitable to
their talents, character, and the time available for study. He could counsel the would-be
airplane mechanic on finding the best places for apprenticeship. He could recommend
books to somebody who wanted to find challenging peers to discuss African history. Like
the network administrator, the pedagogical counselor would conceive of himself as a
professional educator. Access to either could be gained by individuals through the use of
educational vouchers.

The role of the educational initiator or leader, the master or "true" leader, is somewhat
more elusive than that of the professional administrator or the pedagogue. This is so
because leadership is itself hard to define. In practice, an individual is a leader if people
follow his initiative and become apprentices in his progressive discoveries. Frequently,
this involves a prophetic vision of entirely new standards— quite understandable today— in
which present "wrong" will turn out to be "right." In a society which would honor the
right to call assemblies through peer-matching, the ability to take educational initiative on
a specific subject would be as wide as access to learning itself. But, of course, there is a
vast difference between the initiative taken by someone to call a fruitful meeting to
discuss this essay and the ability of someone to provide leadership in the systematic
exploration of its implications.

Leadership also does not depend on being right. As Thomas Kuhn points out, in a period
of constantly changing paradigms most of the very distinguished leaders are bound to be
proven wrong by the test of hindsight. Intellectual leadership does depend on superior
intellectual discipline and imagination and the willingness to associate with others in their
exercise. A learner, for example, may think that there is an analogy between the U.S.
antislavery movement or the Cuban Revolution and what is happening in Harlem. The
educator who is himself a historian can show him how to appreciate the flaws in such an
analogy. He may retrace his own steps as a historian. He may invite the learner to
participate in his own research. In both cases he will apprentice his pupil in a critical art—
which is rare in school— and which money or other favors cannot buy.

The relationship of master and disciple is not restricted to intellectual discipline. It has its
counterpart in the arts, in physics, in religion, in psychoanalysis, and in pedagogy. It fits
mountain-climbing, silverworking and politics, cabinetmaking and personnel
administration. What is common to all true master-pupil relationships is the awareness

Deschooling Society

Page # 70

both share that their relationship is literally priceless and in very different ways a
privilege for both.

Charlatans, demagogues, proselytizers, corrupt masters, and simoniacal priests, tricksters,
miracle workers, and messiahs have proven capable of assuming leadership roles and
thus show the dangers of any dependence of a disciple on the master. Different societies
have taken different measures to defend themselves against these counterfeit teachers.
Indians relied on caste-lineage, Eastern Jews on the spiritual discipleship of rabbis, high
periods of Christianity on an exemplary life of monastic virtue, other periods on
hierarchical orders. Our society relies on certification by schools. It is doubtful that this
procedure provides a better screening, but if it should be claimed that it does, then the
counterclaim can be made that it does so at the cost of making personal discipleship
almost vanish.

In practice, there will always be a fuzzy line between the teacher of skills and the
educational leaders identified above, and there are no practical reasons why access to
some leaders could not be gained by discovering the "master" in the drill teacher who
introduces students to his discipline.

On the other hand, what characterizes the true master-disciple relationship is its priceless
character. Aristotle speaks of it as a ""moral type of friendship, which is not on fixed
terms: it makes a gift, or does whatever it does, as to a friend." Thomas Aquinas says of
this kind of teaching that inevitably it is an act of love and mercy. This kind of teaching is
always a luxury for the teacher and a form of leisure (in Greek, "scliole") for him and his
pupil: an activity meaningful for both, having no ulterior purpose.

To rely for true intellectual leadership on the desire of gifted people to provide it is
obviously necessary even in our society, but it could not be made into a policy now. We
must first construct a society in which personal acts themselves reacquire a value higher
than that of making things and manipulating people. In such a society exploratory,
inventive, creative teaching would logically be counted among the most desirable forms
of leisurely "unemployment." But we do not have to wait until the advent of utopia. Even
now one of the most important consequences of deschooling and the establishment of
peer-matching facilities would be the initiative which "masters" could take to assemble
congenial disciples. It would also, as we have seen, provide ample opportunity for
potential disciples to share information or to select a master.

Schools are not the only institutions which pervert professions by packaging roles.
Hospitals render home care increasingly impossible— and then justify hospitalization as a
benefit to the sick. At the same time, the doctor's legitimacy and ability to work come
increasingly to depend on his association with a hospital, even though he is still less
totally dependent on it than are teachers on schools. The same could be said about courts,
which overcrowd their calendars as new transactions acquire legal solemnity, and thus
delay justice. Or it could be said about churches, which succeed in making a captive
profession out of a free vocation. The result in each case is scarce service at higher cost,
and greater income to the less competent members of the profession.

Deschooling Society

Page# 71

So long as the older professions monopolize superior income and prestige it is difficult to
reform them. The profession of the schoolteacher should be easier to reform, and not only
because it is of more recent origin. The educational profession now claims a
comprehensive monopoly; it claims the exclusive competence to apprentice not only its
own novices but those of other professions as well. This overexpansion renders it
vulnerable to any profession which would reclaim the right to teach its own apprentices.
Schoolteachers are overwhelmingly badly paid and frustrated by the tight control of the
school system. The most enterprising and gifted among them would probably find more
congenial work, more independence, and even higher incomes by specializing as skill
models, network administrators, or guidance specialists.

Finally, the dependence of the registered student on the certified teacher can be broken
more easily than his dependence on other professionals— for instance, that of a
hospitalized patient on his doctor. If schools ceased to be compulsory, teachers who find
their satisfaction in the exercise of pedagogical authority in the classroom would be left
only with pupils who were attracted by their style. The disestablishment of our present
professional structure could begin with the dropping out of the schoolteacher.

The disestablishment of schools will inevitably happen— and it will happen surprisingly
fast. It cannot be retarded very much longer, and it is hardly necessary to promote it
vigorously, for this is being done now. What is worthwhile is to try to orient it in a
hopeful direction, for it could take place in either of two diametrically opposed ways.

The first would be the expansion of the mandate of the pedagogue and his increasing
control over society even outside school. With the best of intentions and simply by
expanding the rhetoric now used in school, the present crisis in the schools could provide
educators with an excuse to use all the networks of contemporary society to funnel their
messages to us— for our own good. Deschooling, which we cannot stop, could mean the
advent of a ""brave new world" dominated by well-intentioned administrators of
programmed instruction.

On the other hand, the growing awareness on the part of governments, as well as of
employers, taxpayers, enlightened pedagogues, and school administrators, that graded
curricular teaching for certification has become harmful could offer large masses of
people an extraordinary opportunity: that of preserving the right of equal access to the
tools both of learning and of sharing with others what they know or believe. But this
would require that the educational revolution be guided by certain goals:

1 . To liberate access to things by abolishing the control which persons and institutions
now exercise over their educational values.

  1. To liberate the sharing of skills by guaranteeing freedom to teach or exercise them on
    request.

Deschooling Society

Page# 72

  1. To liberate the critical and creative resources of people by returning to individual
    persons the ability to call and hold meetings— an ability now increasingly monopolized by
    institutions which claim to speak for the people.

  2. To liberate the individual from the obligation to shape his expectations to the services
    offered by any established profession— by providing him with the opportunity to draw on
    the experience of his peers and to entrust himself to the teacher, guide, adviser, or healer
    of his choice. Inevitably the deschooling of society will blur the distinctions between
    economics, education, and politics on which the stability of the present world order and
    the stability of nations now rest.

Our review of educational institutions leads us to a review of our image of man. The
creature whom schools need as a client has neither the autonomy nor the motivation to
grow on his own. We can recognize universal schooling as the culmination of a
Promethean enterprise, and speak about the alternative as a world fit to live in for
Epimethean man. While we can specify that the alternative to scholastic funnels is a
world made transparent by true communication webs, and while we can specify very
concretely how these could function, we can only expect the Epimethean nature of man
to re-emerge; we can neither plan nor produce it.

Deschooling Society

Page# 73

7

Rebirth of Epimethean Man

Our society resembles the ultimate machine which I once saw in a New York toy shop. It
was a metal casket which, when you touched a switch, snapped open to reveal a
mechanical hand. Chromed fingers reached out for the lid, pulled it down, and locked it
from the inside. It was a box; you expected to be able to take something out of it; yet all it
contained was a mechanism for closing the cover. This contraption is the opposite of
Pandora's "box."

The original Pandora, the All-Giver, was an Earth goddess in prehistoric matriarchal
Greece. She let all ills escape from her amphora (pythos). But she closed the lid before
Hope could escape. The history of modem man begins with the degradation of Pandora's
myth and comes to an end in the self-sealing casket. It is the history of the Promethean
endeavor to forge institutions in order to corral each of the rampant ills. It is the history of
fading hope and rising expectations.

To understand what this means we must rediscover the distinction between hope and
expectation. Hope, in its strong sense, means trusting faith in the goodness of nature,
while expectation, as I will use it here, means reliance on results which are planned and
controlled by man. Hope centers desire on a person from whom we await a gift.
Expectation looks forward to satisfaction from a predictable process which will produce
what we have the right to claim. The Promethean ethos has now eclipsed hope. Survival
of the human race depends on its rediscovery as a social force.

The original Pandora was sent to Earth with ajar which contained all ills; of good things,
it contained only hope. Primitive man lived in this world of hope. He relied on the
munificence of nature, on the handouts of gods, and on the instincts of his tribe to enable
him to subsist. Classical Greeks began to replace hope with expectations. In their version
of Pandora she released both evils and goods. They remembered her mainly for the ills
she had unleashed. And, most significantly, they forgot that the All-Giver was also the
keeper of hope.

The Greeks told the story of two brothers, Prometheus and Epimetheus. The former
warned the latter to leave Pandora alone. Instead, he married her. In classical Greece the
name "Epimetheus," which means "hindsight," was interpreted to mean "dull" or "dumb."

Deschooling Society

Page # 74

By the time Hesiod retold the story in its classical form, the Greeks had become moral
and misogynous patriarchs who panicked at the thought of the first woman. They built a
rational and authoritarian society. Men engineered institutions through which they
planned to cope with the rampant ills. They became conscious of their power to fashion
the world and make it produce services they also learned to expect. They wanted their
own needs and the future demands of their children to be shaped by their artifacts. They
became lawgivers, architects, and authors, the makers of constitutions, cities, and works
of art to serve as examples for their offspring. Primitive man had relied on mythical
participation in sacred rites to initiate individuals into the lore of society, but the classical
Greeks recognized as true men only those citizens who let themselves be fitted by
paidela (education) into the institutions their elders had planned.

The developing myth reflects the transition from a world in which dreams were
interpreted to a world in which oracles were made. From immemorial time, the Earth
Goddess had been worshipped on the slope of Mount Parnassus, which was the center
and navel of the Earth. There, at Delphi (from deiphys, the womb), slept Gaia, the sister
of Chaos and Eros. Her son, Python the dragon, guarded her moonlit and dewy dreams,
until Apollo the Sun God, the architect of Troy, rose from the east, slew the dragon, and
became the owner of Gaia's cave. His priests took over her temple. They employed a
local maiden, sat her on a tripod over Earth's smoking navel, and made her drowsy with
fumes. They then rhymed her ecstatic utterances into hexameters of self-fulfilling
prophecies. From all over the Peloponnesus men brought their problems to Apollo's
sanctuary. The oracle was consulted on social options, such as measures to be taken to
stop a plague or a famine, to choose the right constitution for Sparta or the propitious
sites for cities which later became Byzantium and Chalcedon. The never-erring arrow
became Apollo's symbol. Everything about him became purposeful and useful.

In the Republic, describing the ideal state, Plato already excludes popular music. Only the
harp and Apollo's lyre would be permitted in towns because their harmony alone creates
"the strain of necessity and the strain of freedom, the strain of the unfortunate and the
strain of the fortunate, the strain of courage and the strain of temperance which befit the
citizen." City-dwellers panicked before Pan's flute and its power to awaken the instincts.
Only "the shepherds may play [Pan's] pipes and they only in the country."

Man assumed responsibility for the laws under which he wanted to live and for the
casting of the environment into his own image. Primitive initiation by Mother Earth into
mythical life was transformed into the education (paideia) of the citizen who would feel
at home in the forum.

To the primitive the world was governed by fate, fact, and necessity. By stealing fire
from the gods, Prometheus turned facts into problems, called necessity into question, and
defied fate. Classical man framed a civilized context for human perspective. He was
aware that he could defy fate-nature-environment, but only at his own risk. Contemporary
man goes further; he attempts to create the world in his image, to build a totally man-
made environment, and then discovers that he can do so only on the condition of

Deschooling Society

Page# 75

constantly remaking himself to fit it. We now must face the fact that man himself is at
stake.

Life today in New York produces a very peculiar vision of what is and what can be, and
without this vision life in New York is impossible. A child on the streets of New York
never touches anything which has not been scientifically developed, engineered, planned,
and sold to someone. Even the trees are there because the Parks Department decided to
put them there. The jokes the child hears on television have been programmed at a high
cost. The refuse with which he plays in the streets of Harlem is made of broken packages
planned for somebody else. Even desires and fears are institutionally shaped. Power and
violence are organized and managed: the gangs versus the police. Learning itself is
defined as the consumption of subject matter, which is the result of researched, planned,
and promoted programs. Whatever good there is, is the product of some specialized
institution. It would be foolish to demand something which some institution cannot
produce. The child of the city cannot expect anything which lies outside the possible
development of institutional process. Even his fantasy is prompted to produce science
fiction. He can experience the poetic surprise of the unplanned only through his
encounter with "dirt," blunder, or failure: the orange peel in the gutter, the puddle in the
street, the breakdown of order, program, or machine are the only take-offs for creative
fancy. "Goofing off" becomes the only poetry at hand.

Since there is nothing desirable which has not been planned, the city child soon
concludes that we will always be able to design an institution for our every want. He
takes for granted the power of process to create value. Whether the goal is meeting a
mate, integrating a neighborhood, or acquiring reading skills, it will be defined in such a
way that its achievement can be engineered. The man who knows that nothing in demand
is out of production soon expects that nothing produced can be out of demand. If a moon
vehicle can be designed, so can the demand to go to the moon. Not to go where one can
go would be subversive. It would unmask as folly the assumption that every satisfied
demand entails the discovery of an even greater unsatisfied one. Such insight would stop
progress. Not to produce what is possible would expose the law of "rising expectations"
as a euphemism for a growing frustration gap, which is the motor of a society built on the
coproduction of services and increased demand.

The state of mind of the modem city-dweller appears in the mythical tradition only under
the image of Hell: Sisyphus, who for a while had chained Thanatos (death), must roll a
heavy stone up the hill to the pinnacle of Hell, and the stone always slips from his grip
just when he is about to reach the top. Tantalus, who was invited by the gods to share
their meal, and on that occasion stole their secret of how to prepare all-healing ambrosia,
which bestowed immortality, suffers eternal hunger and thirst standing in a river of
receding waters, overshadowed by fruit trees with receding branches. A world of ever-
rising demands is not just evil-it can be spoken of only as Hell.

Man has developed the frustrating power to demand anything because he cannot visualize
anything which an institution cannot do for him. Surrounded by all-powerful tools, man
is reduced to a tool of his tools. Each of the institutions meant to exorcise one of the

Deschooling Society

Page #76

primeval evils has become a fail-safe, self-sealing coffin for man. Man is trapped in the
boxes he makes to contain the ills Pandora allowed to escape. The blackout of reality in
the smog produced by our tools has enveloped us. Quite suddenly we find ourselves in
the darkness of our own trap.

Reality itself has become dependent on human decision. The same President who ordered
the ineffective invasion of Cambodia could equally well order the effective use of the
atom. The "Hiroshima switch" now can cut the navel of the Earth. Man has acquired the
power to make Chaos overwhelm both Eros and Gaia. This new power of man to cut the
navel of the Earth is a constant reminder that our institutions not only create their own
ends, but also have the power to put an end to themselves and to us. The absurdity of
modern institutions is evident in the case of the military. Modem weapons can defend
freedom, civilization, and life only by annihilating them. Security in military language
means the ability to do away with the Earth.

The absurdity that underlies nonmilitary institutions is no less manifest. There is no
switch in them to activate their destructive power, but neither do they need a switch.

Their grip is already fastened to the lid of the world. They create needs faster than they
can create satisfaction, and in the process of trying to meet the needs they generate, they
consume the Earth. This is true for agriculture and manufacturing, and no less for
medicine and education. Modem agriculture poisons and exhausts the soil. The "green
revolution" can, by means of new seeds, triple the output of an acre— but only with an
even greater proportional increase of fertilizers, insecticides, water, and power.
Manufacturing of these, as of all other goods, pollutes the oceans and the atmosphere and
degrades irreplaceable resources. If combustion continues to increase at present rates, we
will soon consume the oxygen of the atmosphere faster than it can be replaced. We have
no reason to believe that fission or fusion can replace combustion without equal or higher
hazards. Medicine men replace midwives and promise to make man into something else:
genetically planned, pharmacologically sweetened, and capable of more protracted
sickness. The contemporary ideal is a pan-hygienic world: a world in which all contacts
between men, and between men and their world, are the result of foresight and
manipulation. School has become the planned process which tools man for a planned
world, the principal tool to trap man in man s trap. It is sup-posed to shape each man to
an adequate level for playing a part in this world game. Inexorably we cultivate, treat,
produce, and school the world out of existence.

The military institution is evidently absurd. The absurdity of nonmilitary institutions is
more difficult to face. It is even more frightening, precisely because it operates
inexorably. We know which switch must stay open to avoid an atomic holocaust. No
switch detains an ecological Armageddon.

In classical antiquity, man had discovered that the world could be made according to
man's plans, and with this insight he perceived that it was inherently precarious, dramatic
and comical. Democratic institutions evolved and man was presumed worthy of trust
within their framework. Expectations from due process and confidence in human nature

Deschooling Society

Page# 77

kept each other in balance. The traditional professions developed and with them the
institutions needed for their exercise.

Surreptitiously, reliance on institutional process has replaced dependence on personal
good will. The world has lost its humane dimension and reacquired the factual necessity
and fatefulness which were characteristic of primitive times. But while the chaos of the
barbarian was constantly ordered in the name of mysterious, anthropomorphic gods,
today only man's planning can be given as a reason for the world being as it, is. Man has
become the plaything of scientists, engineers, and planners.

We see this logic at work in ourselves and in others. I know a Mexican village through
which not more than a dozen cars drive each day. A Mexican was playing dominoes on
the new hard-surface road in front of his house— where he had probably played and sat
since his youth. A car sped through and killed him. The tourist who reported the event to
me was deeply upset, and yet he said: "The man had it coming to him."

At first sight, the tourist's remark is no different from the statement of some primitive
bushman reporting the death of a fellow who had collided with a taboo and had therefore
died. But the two statements carry opposite meanings. The primitive can blame some
tremendous and dumb transcendence, while the tourist is in awe of the inexorable logic of
the machine. The primitive does not sense responsibility; the tourist senses it, but denies
it. In both the primitive and the tourist the classical mode of drama, the style of tragedy,
the logic of personal endeavor and rebellion is absent. The primitive man has not become
conscious of it, and the tourist has lost it. The myth of the Bushman and the myth of the
American are made of inert, inhuman forces. Neither experiences tragic rebellion. For the
Bushman, the event follows the laws of magic; for the American, it follows the laws of
science. The event puts him under the spell of the laws of mechanics, which for him
govern physical, social, and psychological events.

The mood of 1971 is propitious for a major change of direction in search of a hopeful
future. Institutional goals continuously contradict institutional products. The poverty
program produces more poor, the war in Asia more Vietcong, technical assistance more
underdevelopment. Birth control clinics increase survival rates and boost the population;
schools produce more dropouts; and the curb on one kind of pollution usually increases
another.

Consumers are faced with the realization that the more they can buy, the more deceptions
they must swallow. Until recently it seemed logical that the blame for this pandemic
inflation of dysfunctions could be laid either on the limping of scientific discovery behind
the technological demands or on the perversity of ethnic, ideological, or class enemies.
Both the expectations of a scientific millennium and of a war to end all wars have
declined.

For the experienced consumer, there is no way back to a na*vc reliance on magical
technologies. Too many people have had bad experiences with neurotic computers,
hospital-bred infections, and jams wherever there is traffic on the road, in the air, or on

Deschooling Society

Page# 78

the phone. Only ten years ago conventional wisdom anticipated a better life based on an
increase in scientific discovery. Now scientists frighten children. The moon shots provide
a fascinating demonstration that human failure can be almost eliminated among the
operators of complex systems-yet this does not allay our fears that the human failure to
consume according to instruction might spread out of control.

For the social reformer there is no way back, either, to the assumptions of the forties. The
hope has vanished that the problem of justly distributing goods can be sidetracked by
creating an abundance of them. The cost of the minimum package capable of satisfying
modern tastes has skyrocketed, and what makes tastes modern is their obsolescence prior
even to satisfaction.

The limits of the Earth's resources have become evident. No breakthrough in science or
technology could provide every man in the world with the commodities and services
which are now available to the poor of rich countries. For instance, it would take the
extraction of one hundred times the present amounts of iron, tin, copper, and lead to
achieve such a goal, with even the "lightest" alternative technology.

Finally, teachers, doctors, and social workers realize that their distinct professional
ministrations have one aspect-at least-in common. They create further demands for the
institutional treatments they provide, faster than they can provide service institutions.

Not just some part, but the very logic, of conventional wisdom is becoming suspect. Even
the laws of economy seem unconvincing outside the narrow parameters which apply to
the social, geographic area where most of the money is concentrated. Money is, indeed,
the cheapest currency, but only in an economy geared to efficiency measured in monetary
terms. Both capitalist and Communist countries in their various forms are committed to
measuring efficiency in cost-benefit ratios expressed in dollars. Capitalism flaunts a
higher standard of living as its claim to superiority. Communism boasts of a higher
growth rate as an index of its ultimate triumph. But under either ideology the total cost of
increasing efficiency increases geometrically. The largest institutions compete most
fiercely for resources which are not listed in any inventory: the air, the ocean, silence,
sunlight, and health. They bring the scarcity of these resources to public attention only
when they are almost irremediably degraded. Everywhere nature becomes poisonous,
society inhumane, and the inner life is invaded and personal vocation smothered.

A society committed to the institutionalization of values identifies the production of
goods and services with the demand for such. Education which makes you need the
product is included in the price of the product. School is the advertising agency which
makes you believe that you need the society as it is. In such a society marginal value has
become constantly self-transcendent. It forces the few largest consumers to compete for
the power to deplete the earth, to fill their own swelling bellies, to discipline smaller
consumers, and to deactivate those who still find satisfaction in making do with what
they have. The ethos of nonsatiety is thus at the root of physical depredation, social
polarization, and psychological passivity.

Deschooling Society

Page # 79

When values have been institutionalized in planned and engineered processes, members
of modern society believe that the good life consists in having institutions which define
the values that both they and their society believe they need. Institutional value can be
defined as the level of output of an institution. The corresponding value of man is
measured by his ability to consume and degrade these institutional outputs, and thus
create a new-even higher-demand. The value of institutionalized man depends on his
capacity as an incinerator. To use an image— he has become the idol of his handiworks.
Man now defines himself as the fur-nace which bums up the values produced by his
tools. And there is no limit to his capacity. His is the act of Prometheus carried to an
extreme.

The exhaustion and pollution of the earth's resources is, above all, the result of a
corruption in man's self-image, of a regression in his consciousness. Some would like to
speak about a mutation of collective consciousness which leads to a conception of man as
an organism dependent not on nature and individuals, but rather on institutions. This
institutionalization of substantive values, this belief that a planned process of treatment
ultimately gives results desired by the recipient, this consumer ethos, is at the heart of the
Promethean fallacy.

Efforts to find a new balance in the global milieu depend on the deinstitutionalization of
values.

The suspicion that something is structurally wrong with the vision of homo faber is
common to a growing minority in capitalist, Communist, and "underdeveloped" countries
alike. This suspicion is the shared characteristic of a new elite. To it belong people of all
classes, incomes, faiths, and civilizations. They have 'become wary of the myths of the
majority: of scientific utopias, of ideological diabolism, and of the expectation of the
distribution of goods and services with some degree of equality. They share with the
majority the sense of being trapped. They share with the majority the awareness that most
new policies adopted by broad consensus consistently lead to results which are glaringly
opposed to their stated aims. Yet whereas the Promethean majority of would-be
spacemen still evades the structural issue, the emergent minority is critical of the
scientific dens ex mach ina, the ideological panacea, and the hunt for devils and witches.
This minority begins to formulate its suspicion that our constant deceptions tie us to
contemporary institutions as the chains bound Prometheus to his rock. Hopeful trust and
classical irony (eironeia) must conspire to expose the Promethean fallacy. Prometheus is
usually thought to mean "foresight," or sometimes even "he who makes the North Star
progress." He tricked the gods out of their monopoly of fire, taught men to use it in the
forging of iron, became the god of technologists, and wound up in iron chains.

The Pythia of Delphi has now been replaced by a computer which hovers above panels
and punch cards. The hexameters of the oracle have given way to sixteen-bit codes of
instructions. Man the helmsman has turned the rudder over to the cybernetic machine.

The ultimate machine emerges to direct our destinies. Children phantasize flying their
spacecrafts away from a crepuscular earth.

Deschooling Society

Page # 80

From the perspectives of the Man on the Moon, Prometheus could recognize sparkling
blue Gaia as the planet of Hope and as the Arc of Mankind. A new sense of the finiteness
of the Earth and a new nostalgia now can open man's eyes to the choice of his brother
Epimetheus to wed the Earth with Pandora.

At this point the Greek myth turns into hopeful prophecy because it tells us that the son
of Prometheus was Deucalion, the Helmsman of the Ark who like Noah outrode the
Flood to become the father of a new mankind which he made from the earth with Pyrrha,
the daughter of Epimetheus and Pandora. We are gaining insight into the meaning of the
Pythos which Pandora brought from the gods as being the inverse of the Box: our Vessel
and Ark.

We now need a name for those who value hope above expectations. We need a name for
those who love people more than products, those who believe that

No people are uninteresting. Their fate is
like the chronicle of planets. Nothing in
them is not particular, and planet is
dissimilar from planet.

We need a name for those who love the earth on which each can meet the other,

And if a man lived in obscurity making his
friends in that obscurity, obscurity is not
uninteresting.

We need a name for those who collaborate with their Promethean brother in the lighting
of the fire and the shaping of iron, but who do so to enhance their ability to tend and care
and wait upon the other, knowing that

to each his world is private, and in that
world one excellent minute. And in that
world one tragic minute.

These are private.* [The three quotations are from ""People"' from the book Selected
Poems by Yevgeny Yevtushenko. Translated and with Introduction by Robin Milner
Gulland and Peter Levi. Published by E. P. Dutton & Co. Inc., 1962, and reprinted with
their permission.]

I suggest that these hopeful brothers and sisters be called Epimethean men.

Deschooling Society

Page #81

ABOUT THE AUTHOR

Ivan Illich was bom in Vienna in 1926. He studied theology and philosophy at the
Gregorian University in Rome and obtained a Ph.D. in history at the University of
Salzburg. He came to the United States in 1951, where he served as assistant pastor in an
Irish-Puerto Rican parish in New York City. From 1956 to 1960 he was assigned as vice-
rector to the Catholic University of Puerto Rico, where he organized an intensive training
center for American priests in Latin American culture. Illich was a co-founder of the
widely known and controversial Center for Intercultural Documentation (CIDOC) in
Cuernavaca, Mexico, and since 1964 he has directed research seminars on "Institutional
Alternatives in a Technological Society," with special focus on Latin America. Ivan
Illich's writings have appeared in The New York Review, The Saturday Review, Esprit,
Kuvsbuch, Siempre, America, Commonweal, Epreuves, and Tern PS Modernes.

Deschooling Society

Page # 82